Jump to content

Scientism

From Niidae Wiki

Template:Short description

Scientism is the belief that science and the scientific method are the best or only way to render truth about the world and reality.<ref>Template:Cite web</ref><ref name= Metaphilosophy2020>Template:Cite journal</ref>

While the term was defined originally to mean "methods and attitudes typical of or attributed to natural scientists", some scholars, as well as political and religious leaders, have also adopted it as a pejorative term with the meaning "an exaggerated trust in the efficacy of the methods of natural science applied to all areas of investigation (as in philosophy, the social sciences, and the humanities)".<ref name=Metaphilosophy2020/><ref>Template:Cite web</ref>

Overview

[edit]

Francis Bacon has been viewed by some scholars as an early proponent of scientism,<ref name="Robinson Whitney Trepanier Corey 2019 p. 80">Template:Cite book</ref> but this is a modern assertion as Bacon was a devout Anglican, writing in his Essays, "a little philosophy inclineth man's mind to atheism, but depth in philosophy bringeth men's minds about to religion."<ref>Template:Cite book</ref>

With respect to the philosophy of science, the term scientism frequently implies a critique of the more extreme expressions of logical positivism<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite book</ref> and has been used by social scientists such as Friedrich Hayek,<ref>Template:Cite book</ref> philosophers of science such as Karl Popper,<ref name="Popper-Hacohen">Template:Cite book</ref> and philosophers such as Mary Midgley,<ref name="Beale2019">Template:Cite journal</ref> the later Hilary Putnam,<ref name="Beale2019" /><ref name="Putnam">Template:Cite book</ref> and Tzvetan Todorov<ref>Template:Cite book</ref> to describe (for example) the dogmatic endorsement of scientific methods and the reduction of all knowledge to only that which is measured or confirmatory.<ref name="Outhwaite22">Template:Cite book</ref>

More generally, scientism is often interpreted as science applied "in excess". This use of the term scientism has two senses:

  • The improper use of science or scientific claims.Template:Sfn This usage applies equally in contexts where science might not apply,<ref>Template:Cite encyclopedia</ref> such as when the topic is perceived as beyond the scope of scientific inquiry, and in contexts where there is insufficient empirical evidence to justify a scientific conclusion. It includes an excessive deference to the claims of scientists or an uncritical eagerness to accept any result described as scientific. This can be a counterargument to appeals to scientific authority. It can also address attempts to apply natural science methods and claims of certainty to the social sciences, which Friedrich Hayek described in The Counter-Revolution of Science (1952) as being impossible, because those methods attempt to eliminate the "human factor", while social sciences (including his own topic of economics) mainly concern the study of human action.
  • "The belief that the methods of natural science, or the categories and things recognized in natural science, form the only proper elements in any philosophical or other inquiry",<ref name = "ODP">Template:Cite encyclopedia</ref> or that "science, and only science, describes the world as it is in itself, independent of perspective"<ref name= Putnam/> with a concomitant "elimination of the psychological [and spiritual] dimensions of experience".<ref>Template:Cite web</ref><ref>Template:Cite book</ref> Tom Sorell provides this definition: "Scientism is a matter of putting too high a value on natural science in comparison with other branches of learning or culture."<ref>Template:Cite book</ref> Philosophers such as Alexander Rosenberg have also adopted "scientism" as a name for the opinion that science is the only reliable source of knowledge.<ref name = Rosenberg>Template:Cite book</ref>

It is also sometimes used to describe the universal applicability of the scientific method, and the opinion that empirical science constitutes the most authoritative worldview or the most valuable part of human learning, sometimes to the complete exclusion of other opinions, such as historical, philosophical, economic or cultural opinions. It has been defined as "the view that the characteristic inductive methods of the natural sciences are the only source of genuine factual knowledge and, in particular, that they alone can yield true knowledge about man and society".<ref name= Bullock>Template:Cite encyclopedia</ref> The term scientism is also used by historians, philosophers, and cultural critics to highlight the possible dangers of lapses towards excessive reductionism with respect to all topics of human knowledge.<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref name="The New Republic">Template:Cite magazine</ref><ref>Template:Cite magazine</ref>

For social theorists practising the tradition of Max Weber, such as Jürgen Habermas and Max Horkheimer, the concept of scientism relates significantly to the philosophy of positivism, but also to the cultural rationalization for modern Western civilization.<ref name=Outhwaite22/><ref>Template:Cite book</ref> Ernesto Sabato, physicist and essayist, wrote in his 1951 essay Template:Lang ("Man and mechanism") of the "superstition of science" as the most contradictory of all superstitions,<ref name="Sabato">Template:Cite book</ref> since this would be the "superstition that one should not be superstitious". He wrote: "science had become a new magic and the man in the street believed in it the more the less he understood it".<ref name= "Sabato" />

Definitions

[edit]

Reviewing the references to scientism in the works of contemporary scholars in 2003, Gregory R. PetersonTemplate:Sfn detected two main general themes:

  • It is used to criticize a totalizing opinion of science as if it were capable of describing all reality and knowledge, or as if it were the only true method to acquire knowledge about reality and the nature of things;
  • It is used, often pejoratively,<ref>Template:Citation</ref><ref>Template:Citation</ref><ref>Template:Citation</ref> to denote violations by which the theories and methods of one (scientific) discipline are applied inappropriately to another (scientific or non-scientific) discipline and its domain. An example of this second usage is to term as scientism any attempt to claim science as the only or primary source of human values (a traditional domain of ethics) or as the source of meaning and purpose (a traditional domain of religion and related worldviews).

The term scientism was popularized by F. A. Hayek, who defined it in 1942 as the "slavish imitation of the method and language of Science".<ref name="Hayek1942">Template:Cite journal</ref>

Mathematician Alexander Grothendieck, in his 1971 essay "The New Universal Church", characterized scientism as a religion-like ideology that advocates scientific reductionism, scientific authoritarianism, political technocracy and technological salvation, while denying the epistemological validity of feelings and experiences such as love, emotion, beauty and fulfillment.<ref name=Grothendieck/> He predicted that "in coming years, the chief political dividing line will fall less and less among the traditional division between 'right' and 'left', but increasingly between the adherents of scientism, who advocate 'technological progress at any price', and their opponents, i.e., roughly speaking, those who regard the enhancement of life, in all its richness and variety, as being the supreme value".<ref name=Grothendieck>Template:Cite journal Translated by John Bell.</ref>

E. F. Schumacher, in his A Guide for the Perplexed (1977), criticized scientism as an impoverished world view confined solely to what can be counted, measured and weighed. "The architects of the modern worldview, notably Galileo and Descartes, assumed that those things that could be weighed, measured, and counted were more true than those that could not be quantified. If it couldn't be counted, in other words, it didn't count."<ref>Template:Citation</ref>

In 1979, Karl Popper defined scientism as "the aping of what is widely mistaken for the method of science".<ref>Template:Cite book</ref>

In 2003, Mikael Stenmark proposed the expression scientific expansionism as a synonym of scientism.<ref name="expansionism">Template:Citation</ref> In the Encyclopedia of Science and Religion, he wrote that, while the doctrines that are described as scientism have many possible forms and varying degrees of ambition, they share the idea that the boundaries of science (that is, typically the natural sciences) could and should be expanded so that something that has not been previously considered as a subject pertinent to science can now be understood as part of science (usually with science becoming the sole or the main arbiter regarding this area or dimension).<ref name="expansionism" /> According to Stenmark, the strongest form of scientism states that science does not have any boundaries and that all human problems and all aspects of human endeavor, with due time, will be dealt with and solved by science alone.<ref name="expansionism"/> This idea has also been termed the myth of progress.<ref>Template:Citation</ref>

Intellectual historian T. J. Jackson Lears argued in 2013 that there has been a recent reemergence of "nineteenth-century positivist faith that a reified 'science' has discovered (or is about to discover) all the important truths about human life. Precise measurement and rigorous calculation, in this view, are the basis for finally settling enduring metaphysical and moral controversies." Lears specifically identified Harvard psychologist Steven Pinker's work as falling in this category.<ref>Template:Cite magazine</ref> Philosophers John N. Gray and Thomas Nagel have made similar criticisms against popular works by moral psychologist Jonathan Haidt, atheist author Sam Harris, and writer Malcolm Gladwell.<ref>Template:Cite magazine</ref><ref>Template:Cite magazine</ref><ref>Template:Cite magazine</ref>

Strong and weak scientism

[edit]

There are various ways of classifying kinds of scientism.<ref name= Metaphilosophy2020/><ref>Template:Cite book</ref> Some authors distinguish between strong and weak scientism, as follows:

  • Template:Em: "of all the knowledge we have, scientific knowledge is the only 'real knowledge'"<ref name=":0">Template:Harvnb.</ref> (Moti Mizrahi), or, "the view that some proposition or theory is true and/or rational to believe if and only if it is a scientific proposition or theory"<ref name=":1">Template:Cite book</ref><ref name=":2">Template:Cite book</ref><ref name=":3">Template:Cite book</ref> (J. P. Moreland), or, "only science yields epistemically credible data"<ref name=":4">Template:Cite book</ref> (Michael W. Austin)
  • Template:Em: "of all the knowledge we have, scientific knowledge is the best knowledge"<ref name=":0" /> (Moti Mizrahi), or, "science is the most valuable, most serious, and most authoritative sector of human learning"<ref name=":1" /><ref name=":2" /><ref name=":3" /> (J. P. Moreland), or, "scientific knowledge claims are the most credible knowledge claims"<ref name=":4" /> (Michael W. Austin)

Relevance to debates about science and religion

[edit]

Both religious and non-religious scholars have applied the term scientism to individuals associated with New Atheism.<ref>Template:Citation</ref><ref>Template:Citation</ref> Theologian John Haught argued that philosopher Daniel Dennett and other New Atheists subscribe to a belief system of scientific naturalism, which includes the dogma that "only nature, including humans and our creations, is real: that God does not exist; and that science alone can give us complete and reliable knowledge of reality."<ref>Template:Cite book</ref> Haught argued that this belief system is self-refuting since it requires its adherents to assent to beliefs that violate its own stated requirements for knowledge.<ref>Template:Cite book</ref> Christian philosopher Peter Williams argued in 2013 that it is only by conflating science with scientism that New Atheists feel qualified to "pontificate on metaphysical issues".<ref>Template:Cite book</ref> Daniel Dennett responded to religious criticism of his 2006 book Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon by saying that accusations of scientism "[are] an all-purpose, wild-card smear ... When someone puts forward a scientific theory that [religious critics] really don't like, they just try to discredit it as 'scientism'. But when it comes to facts, and explanations of facts, science is the only game in town".<ref>Template:Citation</ref>

Non-religious scholars have also associated New Atheist thought with scientism and/or with positivism. Atheist philosopher Thomas Nagel argued that philosopher Sam Harris conflated all empirical knowledge with scientific knowledge.<ref>Template:Cite magazine</ref> Marxist literary critic Terry Eagleton argued that Christopher Hitchens possessed an "old-fashioned scientistic notion of what counts as evidence" that reduces knowledge to what can and cannot be proven by scientific procedure.<ref>Template:Cite book</ref> Agnostic philosopher Anthony Kenny has also criticized New Atheist philosopher Alexander Rosenberg's The Atheist's Guide to Reality for resurrecting a self-refuting epistemology of logical positivism and reducing all knowledge of the universe to the discipline of physics.<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>

Michael Shermer, founder of The Skeptics Society, discussed resemblances between scientism and traditional religions, indicating the cult of personality that develops for some scientists. He defined scientism as a worldview that encompasses natural explanations, eschews supernatural and paranormal speculations, and embraces empiricism and reason.<ref>Template:Citation</ref>

The Iranian scholar Seyyed Hossein Nasr has stated that in the Western world, many will accept the ideology of modern science, not as "simple ordinary science", but as a replacement for religion.<ref>Template:Cite book</ref>Template:Page needed

Gregory R. Peterson wrote that "for many theologians and philosophers, scientism is among the greatest of intellectual sins".Template:Sfn Genetic biologist Austin L. Hughes wrote in the conservative journal The New Atlantis that scientism has much in common with superstition: "the stubborn insistence that something ... has powers which no evidence supports."<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>

Repeating common criticisms of logical positivism and verificationism, philosopher of religion Keith Ward has said that scientism is philosophically inconsistent or even self-refuting, as the truth of the two statements "no statements are true unless they can be proven scientifically (or logically)" and "no statements are true unless they can be shown empirically to be true" cannot themselves be proven scientifically, logically, or empirically.<ref>Template:Citation</ref><ref>Template:Cite book</ref>

Philosophy of science

[edit]

Template:Main

Anti-scientism

[edit]

Philosopher Paul Feyerabend, who was an enthusiastic proponent of scientism during his youth,<ref>Template:Cite SEP "Feyerabend's youthful positivist scientism makes quite a contrast with his later conclusions."</ref> later came to characterize science as "an essentially anarchic enterprise"Template:Sfn and argued emphatically that science merits no exclusive monopoly of "dealing in knowledge" and that scientists have never operated within a distinct and narrowly self-defined tradition. In his essay Against Method he depicted the process of contemporary scientific education as a mild form of indoctrination, intended for "making the history of science duller, simpler, more uniform, more 'objective' and more easily accessible to treatment by strict and unchanging rules".Template:Sfn

Template:Blockquote

Pro-scientism

[edit]

Physicist and philosopher Mario Bunge used the term scientism with a favorable rather than pejorative sense in numerous books published during several decades,<ref>Template:Cite book</ref><ref>Template:Cite book</ref><ref name=Bunge2006>Template:Cite book</ref><ref>Template:Cite book</ref> and in articles with titles such as "In Defense of Realism and Scientism"<ref>Template:Cite book</ref> and "In Defense of Scientism".<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref> Bunge said that scientism should not be equated with inappropriate reductionism,<ref name=Bunge2006/> and he dismissed critics of science such as Hayek and Habermas as dogmatists and obscurantists: Template:Blockquote

In 2018, philosophers Maarten Boudry and Massimo Pigliucci co-edited a book titled Science Unlimited? The Challenges of Scientism in which a number of chapters by philosophers and scientists defended scientism.<ref name="BoudryPigliucci2018">Template:Cite book</ref> In his chapter "Two Cheers for Scientism", Taner Edis wrote: Template:Blockquote

Rhetoric of science

[edit]

Template:Main Thomas M. Lessl argued that religious themes persist in what he terms scientism, the public rhetoric of science.<ref name="Lessl1996"/> There are two methods of describing this idea of scientism: the epistemological method (the assumption that the scientific method trumps other ways of knowing) and the ontological method (that the rational mind represents the world and both operate in knowable ways). According to Lessl, the ontological method is an attempt to "resolve the conflict between rationalism and skepticism". Lessl also argued that without scientism, there would not be a scientific culture.<ref name="Lessl1996">Template:Cite journal</ref>

Rationalization and modernity

[edit]

Template:See also In the introduction to his collected works on the sociology of religion, Max Weber asked why "the scientific, the artistic, the political, or the economic development [elsewhere] ... did not enter upon that path of rationalization which is peculiar to the Occident?" According to the German social theorist Jürgen Habermas, "For Weber, the intrinsic (that is, not merely contingent) relationship between modernity and what he called 'Occidental rationalism' was still self-evident." Weber described a process of rationalisation, disenchantment and the "disintegration of religious world views" that resulted in modern secular societies and capitalism.<ref name="Habermas1990">Habermas, Jürgen (1990), The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, Polity Press, Template:ISBN, pp. 2–3.</ref> Template:Blockquote

Habermas is critical of pure instrumental rationality, arguing that the "Social Life–World" of subjective experiencing is better suited to literary expression, whereas the sciences deal with "intersubjectively accessible experiences" that can be generalized in a formal language, while the literary arts "must generate an intersubjectivity of mutual understanding in each concrete case".<ref name="Olson2008">Template:Cite book</ref><ref>Template:Cite book</ref> Habermas quoted writer Aldous Huxley in support of this duality of literature and science: Template:Blockquote

See also

[edit]

Template:Portal Template:Div col

Template:Div col end

References

[edit]

Template:Reflist

Bibliography

[edit]
[edit]

Template:Wiktionary

Template:Navboxes

Template:Authority control