Nyaya
Template:Short description Template:Italic title Template:EngvarB Template:Use dmy dates Template:Hindu philosophy Nyāya (Sanskrit: न्यायः, IAST: nyāyaḥ), literally meaning "justice", "rules", "method" or "judgment",<ref name="mmw" /><ref name="nyabri">Template:Cite web</ref> is one of the six orthodox (Āstika) schools of Hindu philosophy.<ref name="nyabri" /> Nyāya's most significant contributions to Indian philosophy were the systematic development of the theory of logic, methodology, and its treatises on epistemology.<ref>B Gupta (2012), An Introduction to Indian Philosophy: Perspectives on Reality, Knowledge and Freedom, Routledge, Template:ISBN, pages 171–189</ref><ref>PT Raju (1985), Structural Depths of Indian Thought: Toward a Constructive Postmodern Ethics, State University of New York Press, Template:ISBN, page 223</ref>
Nyāya epistemology accepts four out of six pramanas as reliable means of gaining knowledge – pratyakṣa (perception), anumāṇa (inference), upamāna (comparison and analogy) and śabda (word, testimony of past or present reliable experts).<ref name=jag>John A. Grimes, A Concise Dictionary of Indian Philosophy: Sanskrit Terms Defined in English, State University of New York Press, Template:ISBN, page 238</ref><ref name=dpsb>DPS Bhawuk (2011), Spirituality and Indian Psychology (Editor: Anthony Marsella), Springer, Template:ISBN, page 172</ref><ref name=gflood>Gavin Flood, An Introduction to Hinduism, Cambridge University Press, Template:ISBN, page 225</ref> In its metaphysics, Nyāya school is closer to the Vaisheshika school of Hinduism than others.<ref name=nyabri/> It holds that human suffering results from mistakes/defects produced by activity under wrong knowledge (notions and ignorance).<ref>Vassilis Vitsaxis (2009), Thought and Faith, Somerset Hall Press, Template:ISBN, page 131</ref> Moksha (liberation), it states, is gained through right knowledge. This premise led Nyāya to concern itself with epistemology, that is the reliable means to gain correct knowledge and to remove wrong notions. False knowledge is not merely ignorance to Naiyyayikas, it includes delusion. Correct knowledge is discovering and overcoming one's delusions, and understanding true nature of soul, self and reality.<ref>BK Matilal (1997), Logic, Language and Reality: Indian Philosophy and Contemporary Issues, Motilal Banarsidass, Template:ISBN, pages 353–357</ref>
Naiyyayika scholars approached philosophy as a form of direct realism, stating that anything that really exists is in principle humanly knowable. To them, correct knowledge and understanding is different from simple, reflexive cognition; it requires Anuvyavasaya (अनुव्यवसाय, cross-examination of cognition, reflective cognition of what one thinks one knows).<ref name=olil/> An influential collection of texts on logic and reason is the Nyāya Sūtras, attributed to Aksapada Gautama, variously estimated to have been composed between 6th-century BCE and 2nd-century CE.<ref name=jfowlerpor129>Jeaneane Fowler (2002), Perspectives of Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Hinduism, Sussex Academic Press, Template:ISBN, page 129</ref><ref name=bkmxiv>B. K. Matilal "Perception. An Essay on Classical Indian Theories of Knowledge" (Oxford University Press, 1986), p. xiv.</ref>
Nyāya school shares some of its methodology and human suffering foundations with Buddhism; however, a key difference between the two is that Buddhism believes that there is neither a soul nor self;<ref>KN Jayatilleke (2010), Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge, Template:ISBN, pages 246–249, from note 385 onwards;
Steven Collins (1994), Religion and Practical Reason (Editors: Frank Reynolds, David Tracy), State Univ of New York Press, Template:ISBN, page 64; Quote: "Central to Buddhist soteriology is the doctrine of not-self (Pali: anattā, Sanskrit: anātman, the opposed doctrine of ātman is central to Brahmanical thought). Put very briefly, this is the [Buddhist] doctrine that human beings have no soul, no self, no unchanging essence.";
Edward Roer (Translator), Template:Google books, pages 2–4
Katie Javanaud (2013), Is The Buddhist 'No-Self' Doctrine Compatible With Pursuing Nirvana?, Philosophy Now;
John C. Plott et al (2000), Global History of Philosophy: The Axial Age, Volume 1, Motilal Banarsidass, Template:ISBN, page 63, Quote: "The Buddhist schools reject any Ātman concept. As we have already observed, this is the basic and ineradicable distinction between Hinduism and Buddhism".</ref> Nyāya school like some other schools of Hinduism such as Dvaita and Viśiṣṭādvaita believes that there is a soul and self, with liberation (mokṣa) as a state of removal of ignorance, wrong knowledge, the gain of correct knowledge, and unimpeded continuation of self.<ref name=bkm>BK Matilal (1997), Logic, Language and Reality: Indian Philosophy and Contemporary Issues, Motilal Banarsidass, Template:ISBN, pages 354–355</ref><ref>David Ambeul (1998), Ontology in Indian Philosophy, in Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Editor: Edward Craig), Routledge, Template:ISBN, pages 118–127</ref>
Etymology
[edit]Nyaya (न्याय) is a Sanskrit word which means justice, equality for all being, specially a collection of general or universal rules.<ref name=mmw/> In some contexts, it means model, axiom, plan, legal proceeding, judicial sentence, or judgment. Nyaya could also mean, "that which shows the way" tracing its Sanskrit etymology. In the theory of logic, and Indian texts discussing it, the term also refers to an argument consisting of an enthymeme or sometimes for any syllogism.<ref name=mmw>nyAya Monier-Williams' Sanskrit-English Dictionary, Cologne Digital Sanskrit Lexicon, Germany</ref> In philosophical context, Nyaya encompasses propriety, logic and method.<ref>Template:Google books, Hindu Philosophy, Volume 32, page 1260</ref>
Panini, revered Sanskrit grammarian, derives the "Nyaya" from the root "i" which conveys the same meaning as "gam" – to go. "Nyaya" signifying logic is there etymologically identical with "nigama" the conclusion of a syllogism.<ref name="978-81-7110-629-5">The Nyaya Sutras of Gautama (Original Text, English Translation & Commentary) Translated & English Commentary by M.M. Satisa Candra Vidyabhusana Edited with a Sanskrit Preface by Dr. Sukhram Template:ISBN</ref>
Nyaya is related to several other concepts and words used in Indian philosophies: Hetu-vidya (science of causes), Anviksiki (science of inquiry, systematic philosophy), Pramana-sastra (epistemology, science of correct knowledge), Tattva-sastra (science of categories), Tarka-vidya (science of reasoning, innovation, synthesis), Vadartha (science of discussion) and Phakkika-sastra (science of uncovering sophism, fraud, error, finding fakes).<ref>N Sinha (1990), The Nyaya Sutras of Gotama, Motilal Banarsidass, Template:ISBN, see Introduction, pages i–ii</ref> Some of these subsume or deploy the tools of Nyaya.
Development
[edit]Template:Quote box The historical development of Nyāya school is unclear, although Nasadiya hymns of Book 10 Chapter 129 of Rigveda recite its spiritual questions in logical propositions.<ref name="Christian2011" /> In early centuries BCE, states Clooney, the early Nyāya scholars began compiling the science of rational, coherent inquiry and pursuit of knowledge.<ref name="fxc">Francis X. Clooney (2010), Hindu God, Christian God: How Reason Helps Break Down the Boundaries, Oxford University Press, Template:ISBN, pages 18–19, 35–39</ref>
Foundational Text
[edit]Aksapada Gautama composed the Nyāya Sūtras (by 2nd century CE), a foundational text for Nyāya, that primarily discusses logic, methodology and epistemology.<ref name="bkmxiv" /> Gautama is also known as Aksapada and Dirghatapas.<ref>Padmapurana Uttarakhanda, Chapter 263</ref> The names Gotama and Gautama points to the family to which he belonged while the names Aksapada and Dirghatapas refer respectively to his meditative habit and practice of long penance.<ref name="978-81-7110-629-5" /> The people of Mithila (modern Darbhanga in North Bihar) ascribe the foundation of Nyāya philosophy to Gautama, husband of Ahalya, and point out as the place of his birth a village named Gautamasthana where a fair is held every year on the 9th day of the lunar month of Chaitra (March–April). It is situated 28 miles north-east of Darbhanga.<ref name="978-81-7110-629-5" />
Commentarial Tradition
[edit]Concepts in the foundational text, the Nyaya Sutras, were clarified through a tradition of commentaries. Commentaries were also a means to defend the philosophy from misinterpretations by scholars of other traditions.<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>
The Nyāya scholars that followed refined, expanded, and applied the Nyaya Sutras to spiritual questions. While the early Nyaya scholars published little to no analysis on whether supernatural power or God exists, they did apply their insights into reason and reliable means to knowledge to the questions of nature of existence, spirituality, happiness and moksha. Later Nyāya scholars, such as Udayana, examined various arguments on theism and attempted to prove existence of God.<ref name="csharma" /> Other Nyāya scholars offered arguments to disprove the existence of God.<ref name="fxc" /><ref>G. Jha (1919), Original atheism of the Nyaya, in Indian Thought – Proceedings and Transactions of the First Oriental Congress, Vol ii, pages 281–285</ref><ref>Dale Riepe (1979), Indian Philosophy Since Independence, Volume 1, BR Grüner Netherlands, Template:ISBN, page 38</ref>
The most important contribution made by the Nyāya school to Hindu thought has been its treatises on epistemology and system of logic that, subsequently, has been adopted by the majority of the other Indian schools.<ref name=olil>Oliver Leaman (2006), Nyaya, in Encyclopaedia of Asian Philosophy, Routledge, Template:ISBN, pages 405–407</ref>
Metaphysics
[edit]Sixteen categories (padārthas)
[edit]The Nyāya metaphysics recognizes sixteen padarthas or categories and includes all six (or seven) categories of the Vaisheshika in the second one of them, called prameya.<ref>Sharma, C. (1997). A Critical Survey of Indian Philosophy, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, Template:ISBN, p.192</ref>
These sixteen categories are:
- Methods and objects of inquiry
- pramāṇa (valid means of knowledge or knowledge sources),
- prameya (objects of valid knowledge),
- Conditions and the components of inquiry
- saṁśaya (doubt),
- prayojana (aim),
- dṛṣṭānta (example),
- siddhānta (conclusion or accepted position),
- avayava (members of syllogism or inferential components),
- tarka (hypothetical/suppositional reasoning),
- nirṇaya (settlement or certainty),
- Forms of and strategies for debate
- vāda (truth-directed debate),
- jalpa (victory-directed debate),
- vitaṇḍā (destructive debate),
- hetvābhāsa (defective reasons),
- chala (tricks),
- jāti (sophisticated refutation or misleading/futile objections) and
- nigrahasthāna (point of defeat or clinchers).<ref>Hiriyanna, M. (1993, reprint 2000). Outlines of Indian Philosophy, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, Template:ISBN, pp.245,245n</ref><ref name="ch">Chattopadhyaya, D. (1986), Indian Philosophy: A Popular Introduction, People's Publishing House, New Delhi, Template:ISBN, p.163</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>
According to Matthew Dasti and Stephen Phillips, it may be useful to interpret the word jnana as cognition rather than knowledge when studying the Nyāya system.<ref>Template:Cite book</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>
The self
[edit]Nyaya posits that there exists a self distinct from the mind, which is distinct from the body.<ref>Template:Cite book</ref> The self is a nonphysical substance and is not inherently conscious.<ref>Template:Cite book</ref>
Epistemology
[edit]Nyāya treatises on epistemology widely influenced other schools of Hinduism.<ref name="jalo" /> In Nyaya philosophy, knowledge is a type of "awareness event that is in accordance with its object by virtue of having been produced by a well-functioning epistemic instrument."<ref name=":1" /> Pramāṇa, a Sanskrit word, literally is "means of knowledge". It encompasses one or more reliable and valid means by which human beings gain accurate, true knowledge.<ref name=jalo>James Lochtefeld, "Pramana" in The Illustrated Encyclopedia of Hinduism, Vol. 2: N-Z, Rosen Publishing. Template:ISBN, pages 520–521</ref> The focus of Pramana is how correct knowledge can be acquired, how one knows, how one doesn't, and to what extent knowledge pertinent about someone or something can be acquired.<ref name="dpsb"/><ref name=kp>Karl Potter (2002), Presuppositions of India's Philosophies, Motilal Banarsidass, Template:ISBN, pages 25–26</ref> By definition, pramāṇas are factive i.e. they cannot produce false belief. So, while statements can be false, testimony cannot be false. <ref name=":1">Template:Cite journal</ref>
Nyāya scholars accepted four valid means (pramāṇa) of obtaining valid knowledge (prameya) –
- perception (pratyakṣa),
- inference (anumāna),
- comparison (upamāna), and
- word/testimony of reliable sources (śabda).
The Nyāya scholars, along with those from other schools of Hinduism, also developed a theory of error, to methodically establish means to identify errors and the process by which errors are made in human pursuit of knowledge. These include saṁśaya (problems, inconsistencies, doubts) and viparyaya (contrariness, errors)<ref>Karl Potter and Sibajiban Bhattacharya (1994), The Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Volume 6, Princeton University Press, Template:ISBN, page 422</ref> which can be corrected or resolved by a systematic process of tarka (reasoning, technique).<ref>Karl Potter and Sibajiban Bhattacharya (1994), Logical Theory & Gangesa & Other chapters, in The Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Volume 6, Princeton University Press, Template:ISBN, page 69-81, 178–201, 462–466</ref><ref>Gerald Larson and Ram Bhattacharya, The Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies (Editor:Karl Potter), Volume 4, Princeton University Press, Template:ISBN, pages 361–362</ref>
Pratyaksha (perception)
[edit]Pratyakṣa (perception) occupies the foremost position in the Nyāya epistemology. Perception can be of two types, laukika (ordinary) and alaukika (extraordinary).<ref name=tror>Troy Organ, Philosophy and the Self: East and West, Associated University Presse, Template:ISBN, pages 91–94</ref> Ordinary perception is defined by Akṣapāda Gautama in his Nyāya Sutra (I, i.4) as a 'non-erroneous cognition which is produced by the intercourse of sense-organs with the objects'.
Indian texts identify four requirements for correct perception:<ref name=kpmat/> Indriyarthasannikarsa (direct experience by one's sensory organ(s) with the object, whatever is being studied), Avyapadesya (non-verbal; correct perception is not through hearsay, according to ancient Indian scholars, where one's sensory organ relies on accepting or rejecting someone else's perception), Avyabhicara (does not wander; correct perception does not change, nor is it the result of deception because one's sensory organ or means of observation is drifting, defective, suspect) and Vyavasayatmaka (definite; correct perception excludes judgments of doubt, either because of one's failure to observe all the details, or because one is mixing inference with observation and observing what one wants to observe, or not observing what one does not want to observe).<ref name=kpmat>Karl Potter (1977), Meaning and Truth, in Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Volume 2, Princeton University Press, Reprinted in 1995 by Motilal Banarsidass, Template:ISBN, pages 160–168</ref>
Ordinary perception to Nyāya scholars was based on direct experience of reality by eyes, ears, nose, touch and taste.<ref name=tror/> Extraordinary perception included yogaja or pratibha (intuition), samanyalaksanapratyaksa (a form of induction from perceived specifics to a universal), and jnanalaksanapratyaksa (a form of perception of prior processes and previous states of a 'topic of study' by observing its current state).<ref name=tror/><ref>Karl Potter (1977), Meaning and Truth, in Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Volume 2, Princeton University Press, Reprinted in 1995 by Motilal Banarsidass, Template:ISBN, pages 168–169</ref>
Determinate and indeterminate perception
[edit]The Naiyyayika maintains two modes or stages in perception. The first is called nirvikalpa (indeterminate), when one just perceives an object without being able to know its features, and the second savikalpa (determinate), when one is able to clearly know an object.<ref>Karl Potter (1977), Meaning and Truth, in Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Volume 2, Princeton University Press, Reprinted in 1995 by Motilal Banarsidass, Template:ISBN, pages 170–172</ref> All laukika and alaukika pratyakshas are savikalpa, but it is necessarily preceded by an earlier stage when it is indeterminate. Vātsāyana says that if an object is perceived with its name we have determinate perception but if it is perceived without a name, we have indeterminate perception. Jayanta Bhatta says that indeterminate perception apprehends substance, qualities and actions and universals as separate and indistinct, without any association with any names, whereas determinate perception apprehends them all together with a name. There is yet another stage called Pratyabhijñā, when one is able to re-recognise something on the basis of memory.<ref name=c>C Sharma, A Critical Survey of Indian Philosophy, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, Template:ISBN, pages192-196</ref>
Anumāna (inference)
[edit]Anumāna (inference) is one of the most important contributions of the Nyāya. It can be of two types: inference for oneself (Svarthanumana, where one does not need any formal procedure, and at the most the last three of their 5 steps), and inference for others (Parathanumana, which requires a systematic methodology of 5 steps). Inference can also be classified into 3 types: Purvavat (inferring an unperceived effect from a perceived cause), Sheshavat (inferring an unperceived cause from a perceived effect) and Samanyatodrishta (when inference is not based on causation but on uniformity of co-existence). A detailed analysis of error is also given, explaining when anumana could be false.<ref name=c/>
Theory of inference
[edit]The methodology of inference involves a combination of induction and deduction by moving from particular to particular via generality. It has five steps, as in the example shown:<ref>Template:Citation</ref><ref name="TS-AB">Template:Cite book</ref>
- There is fire on the hill (called Pratijñā, required to be proved)
- Because there is smoke there (called Hetu, reason)
- Wherever there is smoke, there is fire, e.g. in a kitchen (called Udāhārana, example of vyāpti)
- The hill has smoke that is pervaded by fire (called Upanaya, reaffirmation or application)
- Therefore, there is fire on the hill (called Nigamana, conclusion)
In Nyāya terminology for this example, the hill would be the paksha (minor term),<ref name="TS-AB"/>Template:Rp the fire is the sādhya (major term),<ref name="TS-AB"/>Template:Rp the smoke is hetu,<ref name="TS-AB"/>Template:Rp and the relationship between the smoke and the fire is vyapti(middle term).<ref name="TS-AB"/>Template:Rp
Hetu further has five characteristics<ref name="Matilal">Template:Cite book</ref>
- It must be present in the Paksha (the case under consideration),
- It must be present in all positive instances (sapaksha, or homologues),
- It must be absent in all negative instances
- It must not be incompatible with an established truth, (abādhitatva)
- Absence of another evidence for the opposite thesis (asatpratipakshitva)
Inference Fallacies (hetvābhasa)
[edit]The fallacies in Anumana (hetvābhasa) may occur due to the following<ref name="Jadunath">Template:Cite book</ref>
- Asiddha: It is the unproved hetu that results in this fallacy.
- Ashrayasiddha: If Paksha [minor term] itself is unreal, then there cannot be locus of the hetu. e.g. The sky-lotus is fragrant, because it is a lotus like any other lotus.
- Svarupasiddha: Hetu cannot exist in paksa at all. E.g. Sound is a quality, because it is visible.
- Vyapyatvasiddha: Conditional hetu. `Wherever there is fire, there is smoke'. The presence of smoke is due to wet fuel.
- Savyabhichara: This is the fallacy of irregular hetu.
- Sadharana: The hetu is too wide. It is present in both sapaksa and vipaksa. `The hill has fire because it is knowable'.
- Asadharana: The hetu is too narrow. It is only present in the Paksha, it is not present in the Sapaksa and in the Vipaksha. `Sound is eternal because it is audible'.
- Anupasamhari: Here the hetu is non-exclusive. The hetu is all-inclusive and leaves nothing by way of sapaksha or vipaksha. e.g. 'All things are non-ternal, because they are knowable'.
- Satpratipaksa: Here the hetu is contradicted by another hetu. If both have equal force, then nothing follows. 'Sound is eternal, because it is audible', and 'Sound is non-eternal, because it is produced'. Here 'audible' is counterbalanced by 'produced' and both are of equal force.
- Badhita: When another proof (as by perception) definitely contradicts and disproves the middle term (hetu). 'Fire is cold because it is a substance'.
- Viruddha: Instead of proving something it is proving the opposite. 'Sound is eternal because it is produced'.
Upamāna (comparison, analogy)
[edit]Upamāna (उपमान) means comparison and analogy.<ref name=dpsb/><ref name="gflood"/> Upamāna, states Lochtefeld,<ref name=jl721/> may be explained with the example of a traveller who has never visited lands or islands with endemic population of wildlife. He or she is told, by someone who has been there, that in those lands you see an animal that sort of looks like a cow, grazes like cow but is different from a cow in such and such way. Such use of analogy and comparison is, state the Indian epistemologists, a valid means of conditional knowledge, as it helps the traveller identify the new animal later.<ref name=jl721>James Lochtefeld, "Upamana" in The Illustrated Encyclopedia of Hinduism, Vol. 2: N-Z, Rosen Publishing. Template:ISBN, page 721</ref> The subject of comparison is formally called upameyam, the object of comparison is called upamānam, while the attribute(s) are identified as sāmānya.<ref name=mw457>Monier Williams (1893), Indian Wisdom – Religious, Philosophical and Ethical Doctrines of the Hindus, Luzac & Co, London, pages 457–458</ref> Thus, explains Monier Williams, if a boy says "her face is like the moon in charmingness", "her face" is upameyam, the moon is upamānam, and charmingness is sāmānya. The 7th century text Bhaṭṭikāvya in verses 10.28 through 10.63 discusses many types of comparisons and analogies, identifying when this epistemic method is more useful and reliable, and when it is not.<ref name=mw457/> In various ancient and medieval texts of Hinduism, 32 types of Upamāna and their value in epistemology are debated.Template:Citation needed
Śabda (word, testimony)
[edit]Śabda (शब्द) means relying on word, testimony of past or present reliable experts.<ref name=dpsb/><ref name=eliottjag>
- Eliott Deutsche (2000), in Philosophy of Religion : Indian Philosophy Vol 4 (Editor: Roy Perrett), Routledge, Template:ISBN, pages 245–248;
- John A. Grimes, A Concise Dictionary of Indian Philosophy: Sanskrit Terms Defined in English, State University of New York Press, Template:ISBN, page 238</ref> Hiriyanna explains Sabda-pramana as a concept which means testimony of a reliable and trustworthy person (āptavākya). The schools of Hinduism which consider it epistemically valid suggest that a human being needs to know numerous facts, and with the limited time and energy available, he can learn only a fraction of those facts and truths directly.<ref name=mhir>M. Hiriyanna (2000), The Essentials of Indian Philosophy, Motilal Banarsidass, Template:ISBN, page 43</ref> He must rely on others, his parent, family, friends, teachers, ancestors and kindred members of society to rapidly acquire and share knowledge and thereby enrich each other's lives. This means of gaining proper knowledge is either spoken or written, but through Sabda (words).<ref name=mhir/> The reliability of the source is important, and legitimate knowledge can only come from the Sabda of reliable sources.<ref name=eliottjag/><ref name=mhir/> The disagreement between the schools of Hinduism has been on how to establish reliability. Some schools, such as Carvaka, state that this is never possible, and therefore Sabda is not a proper pramana. Other schools debate means to establish reliability.<ref>P. Billimoria (1988), Śabdapramāṇa: Word and Knowledge, Studies of Classical India Volume 10, Springer, Template:ISBN, pages 1–30</ref>
Testimony can be of two types, Vaidika (Vedic), which are the words of the four sacred Vedas, and Laukika, or words and writings of trustworthy human beings. Vaidika testimony is preferred over Laukika testimony. Laukika-sourced knowledge must be questioned and revised as more trustworthy knowledge becomes available.<ref name="SC-Nyaya">Template:Cite book</ref><ref name="KLD-LnO">Template:Cite book</ref><ref name="Aphor-Gau">Template:Cite book</ref>
Direct Realism
[edit]In Nyaya philosophy, direct realism asserts that our cognitions are informational states revealing external objects. According to Nyaya, the world consists of stable, three-dimensional objects, and their system of categories accurately mirrors reality's structure. Nyaya philosophy emphasizes the importance of universals, qualities, and relations in understanding the organization of the world. These foundational elements are believed to play essential roles in determining the phenomenological, causal, and logical organization of the world, playing a crucial role in the classification of objects.<ref>Template:Cite book</ref>
Comparison with other schools of Hinduism
[edit]Each school of Hinduism has its own treatises on epistemology, with different number of Pramanas. For example, compared to Nyāya school's four pramanas, Carvaka school has just one (perception), while Advaita Vedanta school recognizes six means to reliable knowledge.<ref name="jag"/><ref name="eliottjag"/>
Theory of causation
[edit]Template:Quote box A cause is defined as an unconditional and invariable antecedent of an effect and an effect as an unconditional and invariable consequent of a cause. The same cause produces the same effect; and the same effect is produced by the same cause. The cause is not present in any hidden form whatsoever in its effect.
The following conditions should be met:
- The cause must be antecedent [Purvavrtti]
- Invariability [Niyatapurvavrtti]
- Unconditionality [Ananyathasiddha]
Nyaya recognizes five kinds of accidental antecedents [Anyathasiddha]
- Mere accidental antecedent. E.g., The colour of the potter's cloth.
- Remote cause is not a cause because it is not unconditional. E.g., The father of the potter.
- The co-effects of a cause are not causally related.
- Eternal substances, or eternal conditions are not unconditional antecedents, e.g. space.
- Unnecessary things, e.g. the donkey of the potter.
Nyaya recognizes three kinds of cause:
- Samavayi, material cause, e.g. thread of a cloth.
- Asamavayi, colour of the thread which gives the colour of the cloth.
- Nimitta, efficient cause, e.g. the weaver of the cloth.
Anyathakhyativada (theory of error)
[edit]The Nyāya theory of error is similar to that of Kumarila's Viparita-khyati (see Mimamsa). The Naiyyayikas also believe, like Kumarila, that error is due to a wrong synthesis of the presented and represented objects. The represented object is confused with the presented one. The word 'anyatha' means 'elsewise' and 'elsewhere' and both of these meanings are brought out in error. The presented object is perceived elsewise and the represented object exists elsewhere. They further maintain that knowledge is not intrinsically valid but becomes so due to extraneous conditions (paratah pramana during both validity and invalidity).
On God and liberation
[edit]Early Naiyyayikas wrote very little about Ishvara (literally, the Supreme Soul). Evidence available suggests that early Nyāya scholars were non-theistic or atheists.<ref>John Clayton (2010), Religions, Reasons and Gods: Essays in Cross-cultural Philosophy of Religion, Cambridge University Press, Template:ISBN, page 150</ref><ref>G Oberhammer (1965), Zum problem des Gottesbeweises in der Indischen Philosophie, Numen, 12: 1–34</ref> Later, and over time, Nyāya scholars tried to apply some of their epistemological insights and methodology to the question: does God exist? Some offered arguments against and some in favor.<ref name=fxc/>
Arguments that God does not exist
[edit]In Nyāya Sūtra's Book 4, Chapter 1, verses 19–21, postulates God exists, states a consequence, then presents contrary evidence, and from contradiction concludes that the postulate must be invalid.<ref name=fxc2/>
A literal interpretation of the three verses suggests that Nyāya school rejected the need for a God for the efficacy of human activity. Since human action and results do not require assumption or need of the existence of God, sutra IV.1.21 is seen as a criticism of the "existence of God and theism postulate".<ref name=fxc2/> The context of the above verses includes various efficient causes. Nyāya Sūtra verses IV.1.22 to IV.1.24, for example, examine the hypothesis that "random chance" explains the world, after these Indian scholars had rejected God as the efficient cause.<ref name=fxc/>
Arguments that God exists
[edit]In Nyayakusumanjali, Udayana gives the following nine arguments to prove the existence of creative God and also refutes the existing objections and questions by atheistic systems of Carvaka, Mimamsa, Buddhists, Jains and Samkhya:<ref name=csharma>Sharma, C. (1997). A Critical Survey of Indian Philosophy, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, Template:ISBN, pp.209–10</ref>
- Kāryāt (lit. "from effect"): The world is an effect. All effects have efficient cause. Hence the world must have an efficient cause. That efficient cause is God.<ref name=csharma/>
- Āyojanāt (lit., from combination): Atoms are inactive. To form a substance, they must combine. To combine, they must move. Nothing moves without intelligence and source of motion. Since we perceive substance, some intelligent source must have moved the inactive atoms. That intelligent source is God.<ref name=csharma/>
- Dhŗtyādéḥ (lit., from support): Something sustains this world. Something destroys this world. Unintelligent Adrsta (unseen principles of nature) cannot do this. We must infer that something intelligent is behind. That is God.<ref name=csharma/>
- Padāt (lit., from word): Each word has meaning and represents an object. This representational power of words has a cause. That cause is God.
- Pratyayataḥ (lit, from faith): Vedas are infallible. Human beings are fallible. Infallible Vedas cannot have been authored by fallible human beings. Someone authored the infallible Vedas. That author is God.<ref name=csharma/>
- Shrutéḥ (lit., from scriptures): The infallible Vedas testify to the existence of God. Thus God exists.<ref name=csharma/>
- Vākyāt (lit., from precepts): Vedas deal with moral laws. These are divine. Divine injunctions and prohibitions can only come from a divine creator of laws. That divine creator is God.<ref name=csharma/>
- Samkhyāviśeşāt (lit., from the specialty of numbers): By rules of perception, only number "one" can ever be directly perceived. All other numbers other than one, are inferences and concepts created by consciousness. When man is born, his mind is incapable of inferences and concepts. He develops consciousness as he develops. The consciousness development is self-evident and proven because of man's ability with perfect numerical conception. This ability to conceive numerically perfect concepts must depend on something. That something is divine consciousness. So God must exist.<ref name=csharma/>
- Adŗşţāt (lit., from the unforeseen): Everybody reaps the fruits of his own actions. Merits and demerits accrue from his own actions. An Unseen Power keeps a balance sheet of the merit and demerit. But since this Unseen Power is Unintelligent, it needs intelligent guidance to work. That intelligent guide is God.<ref name=csharma/>
Naiyyayikas characterize Ishvara as absent of adharma, false knowledge, and error; and possessing dharma, right knowledge, and equanimity. Additionally, Ishvara is omnipotent and acts in a way that is good for his creatures.<ref>Template:Cite book</ref>
Liberation
[edit]The Naiyyayikas believe that the bondage of the world is due to false knowledge, which can be removed by constantly thinking of its opposite (pratipakshabhavana), namely, the true knowledge.<ref>Dasgupta, Surendranath (1975). A History of Indian Philosophy, Vol. I, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, Template:ISBN, p.365</ref> The opening aphorism of the Template:IAST states that only the true knowledge leads to niḥśreyasa (liberation).<ref name=ch/> However, the Nyāya school also maintains that God's grace is essential for obtaining true knowledge.<ref>Sharma, C. (1997). A Critical Survey of Indian Philosophy, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, Template:ISBN, p.208</ref> Jayanta, in his Nyayamanjari describes salvation as a passive stage of the self in its natural purity, unassociated with pleasure, pain, knowledge and willingness.<ref>Dasgupta, Surendranath (1975). A History of Indian Philosophy, Vol. I, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, Template:ISBN, p.366</ref>
Literature
[edit]In the Yājñavalkya Smṛti, Nyāya is mentioned as one of the fourteen principal branches of learning. The Matsya-Purāṇa states that knowledge of Nyāya came from the mouth of Brahmā. The Mahābhārata also mentions principles of Nyāya.<ref name=":0">Template:Cite thesis</ref>
The earliest text of the Nyāya School is the Template:IAST of [[Akṣapāda Gautama|Template:IAST]]. The text is divided into five books, each having two sections. Vatsyayana's Template:IAST is a classic commentary on the Template:IAST. Udyotakara's Template:IAST (6th century CE) is written to defend Template:IAST against the attacks made by Dignāga. [[Vacaspati Misra|Template:IAST]]'s Template:IAST (9th century CE) is the next major exposition of this school. Two other texts, Template:IAST and Template:IAST are also attributed to him. Udayana's (984 CE) Template:IAST is an important commentary on Template:IAST's treatise. His Template:IAST is the first systematic account of theistic Template:IAST. His other works include Template:IAST, Template:IAST and Template:IAST. Jayanta Bhatta's Template:IAST (10th century CE) is basically an independent work. Bhasarvajna's Nyayasara (10th century CE) is a survey of Template:IAST philosophy.<ref>Radhakrishnan, S. Indian Philosophy, Vol. II, Oxford University Press, New Delhi, 2006, Template:ISBN, pp.36–40</ref>
The later works on Template:IAST accepted the [[Vaisheshika|Template:IAST]] categories and Template:IAST's Template:IAST (12th century CE) is a notable treatise of this syncretist school. Template:IAST's Template:IAST (13th century CE) is another important work of this school.<ref>Radhakrishnan, S. Indian Philosophy, Vol. II, Oxford University Press, New Delhi, 2006, Template:ISBN, p.40</ref>
Template:IAST's Template:IAST (14th century CE) is the first major treatise of the new school of Template:IAST. His son, Template:IAST's Template:IAST, though a commentary on Udayana's Template:IAST, incorporated his father's views. Jayadeva wrote a commentary on [[Tattvacintāmaṇi|Template:IAST]] known as Template:IAST (14th century CE). Template:IAST's Template:IAST (16th century CE) is first great work of Navadvipa school of Template:IAST. [[Raghunatha Siromani|Template:IAST]]'s Template:IAST and Template:IAST are the next important works of this school. [[Visvanatha Panchanana Bhattacharya|Template:IAST]]'s Template:IAST (17th century CE) is also a notable work.<ref name="Radhakrishnan, S. 2006, p.41">Radhakrishnan, S. Indian Philosophy, Vol. II, Oxford University Press, New Delhi, 2006, Template:ISBN, p.41</ref> The Commentaries on Template:IAST by Jagadish Tarkalankar (17th century CE) and Gadadhar Bhattacharya (17th century CE) are the last two notable works of this school.
[[Annambhatta|Template:IAST]] (17th century CE) tried to develop a consistent system by combining the ancient and the new schools, Template:IAST and Template:IAST and Template:IAST to develop the Template:IAST school. His Template:IAST and Template:IAST are the popular manuals of this school.<ref name="Radhakrishnan, S. 2006, p.41"/>
Nyāya Influence on Buddhism
[edit]While initially distinct from Buddhism, Nyāya's rigorous approach to reasoning and epistemology profoundly influenced the development of Buddhist philosophy, particularly in the areas of logical analysis, epistemology, and the structure of doctrinal debates.
Nyāya and Buddhist Epistemology
[edit]The influence of Nyāya on Buddhist epistemology is profound, especially in the development of the four major pramāṇa (valid means of knowledge). Below is a breakdown of how Buddhist thinkers integrated and adapted Nyāya concepts in their philosophical systems:
Nyāya Concept | Buddhist Adaptation | Key Buddhist Thinkers & Texts |
---|---|---|
Perception (pratyakṣa) | Buddhism expanded the concept of perception to include not just sensory data but also insight into phenomena's impermanence and interdependence. | Dharmakīrti's Pramāṇavārttika emphasizes direct perception to analyze impermanence and the non-self. |
Inference (anumāna) | Buddhist philosophers, particularly Dharmakīrti, used inference to establish causality and to demonstrate the non-essential nature of self and phenomena. | Nāgārjuna's arguments against inherent existence use inference to show that all things depend on causes and conditions (dependent origination). |
Comparison (upamāna) | Analogies are used extensively in Buddhist texts to illustrate complex, abstract ideas such as emptiness (śūnyatā). | Used by early Madhyamaka thinkers to clarify ideas of non-self and impermanence, and by Vasubandhu to elucidate the nature of consciousness. |
Testimony (śabda) | The Buddha’s teachings are treated as authoritative testimony, much like sacred texts in Nyāya. In Buddhism, this is used to validate the path to liberation (nirvāṇa). | Yogācāra texts often stress the importance of authoritative testimony (śabda) to understand the nature of consciousness and the path to enlightenment. |
Nyāya and Buddhist Logic
[edit]Another significant area of influence was in the domain of logic. Nyāya's formal system of inference (anumāna) directly impacted Buddhist logic, especially in the works of scholars like Dharmakīrti. Nyāya's focus on hetu (reasoning or cause) and the structure of valid arguments was adopted and modified by Buddhists in their development of logical proofs (pramāṇa) to support doctrines like impermanence and non-self.
In the Pramāṇavārttika, Dharmakīrti reinterpreted Nyāya’s logical tools to fit within Buddhist metaphysical views. For example, Nyāya’s approach to inference was used to argue against essentialist doctrines by showing that all phenomena are dependent on causes and conditions (dependent origination), rather than existing inherently (svabhāva). In Mādhyamika philosophy, Nāgārjuna and Śāntideva also employed logic and dialectical reasoning, heavily influenced by Nyāya, to argue against Nyāya’s own concept of an unchanging self.
Nyāya and Buddhist Debate Practices
[edit]The formal practice of debate (yukti) in Buddhist scholasticism, especially within monastic institutions, reflects the influence of Nyāya. The rigorous techniques of formal reasoning and logical debate in Nyāya were adopted by Buddhists to engage in systematic argumentation, not only with other philosophical schools but also within their own traditions.
Buddhist monastic institutions, particularly in India, followed a debate structure built on Nyāya’s epistemological principles, emphasizing the importance of valid reasoning and evidence in defending doctrinal views. These debates often centered around the validity of pramāṇas and the nature of reality (impermanence and non-self versus permanence and self). In Tibet and East Asia, these debates became central to the scholastic tradition and helped refine Buddhist thought over centuries.
Nyāya Influence in Later Buddhist Traditions
[edit]The impact of Nyāya was not confined to early Indian Buddhist thinkers but continued to shape later Buddhist traditions. For example, Tibetan Buddhism developed sophisticated methods of debate and logic that were heavily influenced by Indian Nyāya. In the Gelug school, the Pramāṇa texts of Dharmakīrti became a central part of the curriculum, alongside Nyāya texts.
In addition, Zen Buddhism and Chan Buddhism also exhibited traces of logical techniques influenced by the early scholastics of India, where rational discourse was used to sharpen the practitioner's understanding of emptiness (śūnyatā) and impermanence.
B.K. Matilal's Contributions to the Study of Nyāya and Buddhism
[edit]B.K. Matilal, a renowned scholar of Indian philosophy, was instrumental in highlighting the intellectual connections between Nyāya and Buddhist epistemology. In his work, Matilal emphasizes how Buddhist philosophers like Dharmakīrti incorporated and adapted Nyāya’s logical frameworks to argue for impermanence and non-self. Matilal further discusses how Buddhists criticized Nyāya’s essentialism, using formal logic and reasoning to refute Nyāya's claims about the permanence of the self and the inherent nature of things.
Matilal’s analysis of these philosophical interactions shows that, despite their doctrinal differences, Nyāya and Buddhism shared a common interest in developing systematic methods of reasoning and argumentation. His work underscores how both traditions engaged in a shared intellectual project of refining methods of knowledge acquisition and logical analysis, even as they differed on metaphysical views.
Table of Nyāya Influence on Buddhist Thought
[edit]To illustrate the extent of Nyāya’s influence on Buddhist philosophy, the following table highlights key concepts adopted and adapted by Buddhist scholars:
Nyāya Concept | Buddhist Adaptation | Example in Buddhist Philosophy |
---|---|---|
Pramāṇa (valid means of knowledge) | Developed into a Buddhist framework of epistemology, focusing on perception, inference, testimony, and comparison. | Dharmakīrti's epistemology in the *Pramāṇavārttika*. |
Perception (pratyakṣa) | Emphasized impermanence and the changing nature of phenomena, incorporating insight into dependent origination. | Used to argue that all things are transient (impermanent). |
Inference (anumāna) | Used for analyzing causality and arguing for emptiness and the absence of an inherent self. | Nāgārjuna's logical refutations of svabhāva (inherent existence). |
Comparison (upamāna) | Employed as a method to explain abstract philosophical concepts through analogy. | Used in early Buddhist texts to explain complex doctrines. |
Testimony (śabda) | The Buddha's teachings (Dharma) were treated as authoritative testimony. | Central to many Buddhist schools of thought, especially in the Yogācāra tradition. |
Logic of Debate (yukti) | Adopted in monastic debate traditions, leading to the development of Buddhist scholasticism. | Central to Indian, Tibetan, and East Asian Buddhist institutions. |
Further Developments and Synthesis
[edit]In addition to Dharmakīrti and Nāgārjuna, Buddhist thinkers like Vasubandhu and Śāntideva also utilized Nyāya-derived logic in their writings. Vasubandhu's work in the Abhidharma tradition integrated Nyāya’s inference and perception frameworks to argue for emptiness and the illusion of permanence in all things.
Moreover, Tibetan Buddhist scholars like Chandrakirti and Jamyang Zhépa further developed these ideas, showing that the dialogue between Nyāya and Buddhism was not a one-way flow but rather an ongoing intellectual exchange that continued across centuries and geographical regions.
Commentaries on the Nyaya-Sutra
[edit]Numerous commentaries have been written on Nyāya-Sutra since its composition. Some of these commentaries are available on www.archive.org for reference. A few of the commentaries are mentioned below:<ref>Template:Cite book</ref>
- Nyaya-Sutra by Gotama or Aksapada
- Nyaya-Bhasya by Vatsyayana
- Nyaya-Varttika by Udyotakar
- Nyaya-Varttika tatparya-tika by Vacaspati Misra
- Nyaya-Varttika-tatparayatika-parisuddhi by Udayans
- Parisuddhiprakasa by Vardhamana
- Vardhamanedu by Padmanabha Misra
- Nyayalankara by Srikantha
- Nyayalankara Vrtti by Jayanta
- Nyaya-manjari by Jayanta
- Nyaya-Vrtti by Abhayatilakopadhyaya
- Nyaya-Vrtti by Visvanatha
- Mitabhasini Vrtti by Mahadeva Vedanti
- Nyayaprakasa by Kesava Misra
- Nyayabodhini by Govardhana
- Nyaya Sutra Vyakhya by Mathuranatha
Differences from Western Philosophy
[edit]Template:Lead rewrite Template:Original research Template:More citations needed
A priori knowledge
[edit]Nyaya philosophy does not establish a category of a priori knowledge. This choice may be due to only considering de re knowledge, not de dicto knowledge.<ref>Template:Cite book</ref>
Logic
[edit]The essential features of logic in the Western tradition are well captured in the following statement by a famous logician Alonzo Church:
Thus, the basic features of Western logic are: It deals with a study of ‘propositions’, specially their ‘logical form’ as abstracted from their ‘content’ or ‘matter’. It deals with ‘general conditions of valid inference’, wherein the truth or otherwise of the premises have no bearing on the ‘logical soundness or validity’ of an inference. It achieves this by taking recourse to a symbolic language that has little to do with natural languages. The main concern of Western logic, in its entire course of development, has been one of systematising patterns of mathematical reasoning, with the mathematical objects being thought of as existing either in an independent ideal world or in a formal domain. Indian logic however, does not deal with ideal entities, such as propositions, logical truth as distinguished from material truth, or with purely symbolic languages that apparently have nothing to do with natural languages.
The central concern of Indian logic as founded in nyāya is epistemology, or the theory of knowledge. Thus Indian logic is not concerned merely with making arguments in formal mathematics rigorous and precise, but attends to the much larger issue of providing rigour to the arguments encountered in natural sciences (including mathematics, which in Indian tradition has the attributes of a natural science and not that of a collection of context free formal statements), and in philosophical discourse. Inference in Indian logic is ‘deductive and inductive’, ‘formal as well as material’. In essence, it is the method of scientific enquiry. Indian ‘formal logic’ is thus not ‘formal’, in the sense generally understood: in Indian logic ‘form’ cannot be entirely separated from ‘content’. In fact, great care is exercised to exclude from logical discourse terms, which have no referential content. No statement, which is known to be false, is admitted as a premise in a valid argument. Thus, the ‘method of indirect proof’ (reductio ad absurdum) is not accepted as a valid method−neither in Indian philosophy nor in Indian mathematics−for proving the existence of an entity whose existence is not demonstrable (even in principle) by other (direct) means of proof.
Indian logic does not make any attempt to develop a purely symbolic and content independent or ‘formal language’ as the vehicle of logical analysis. Instead, what Indian logic, especially in its later phase of Navya-Nyāya starting with the work of Gāngeśa Upādhyāya of the 14th century, has developed is a technical language, which is based on the natural language Sanskrit, yet avoids ‘inexactness’ and ‘misleading irregularities’ by various technical devices. This technical language, being based on the natural language Sanskrit, inherits a certain natural structure and interpretation, and sensitivity to the context of enquiry. On the other hand, the symbolic formal systems of Western logic, though considerably influenced in their structure (say, in quantification, etc.) by the basic patterns discernible in European languages, are professedly purely symbolic, carrying no interpretation whatsoever−such interpretations are supposed to be supplied separately in the specific context of the particular field of enquiry ‘employing’ the symbolic formal system.<ref>Template:Cite web</ref>
See also
[edit]Template:Portal Template:Div col
- Nyāya Sūtras
- Ancient Mithila University
- Gautama Buddha
- Gautama Maharishi
- Hindu philosophy
- List of teachers of Nyaya
- Neti neti "not this", "neither this" (neti is sandhi from na-iti "not so").
- Śāstra pramāṇam in Hinduism
- Tarka-Sangraha
- Padārtha
- Vaisheshika#The Categories or Padārtha
- Categories (Aristotle)
References
[edit]Further reading
[edit]- Kisor Kumar Chakrabarti (1995), Definition and induction: a historical and comparative study, University of Hawaii Press, Template:ISBN, Template:Oclc
- Gangesa (2010), Classical Indian philosophy of induction: the Nyāya viewpoint, (Translator: Kisor Kumar Chakrabarti), Template:ISBN, Template:Oclc
- Gangesa (2020), Tattva-cintā-maṇi, (“Jewel”), translated by Stephen Phillips, Jewel of Reflection on the Truth about Epistemology. 3 volumes, London: Bloomsbury.
- Gopi Kaviraj (1961), Gleanings from the history and bibliography of the Nyaya-Vaisesika literature, Indian Studies: Past & Present, Template:Oclc
- Arthur Keith (1921), Indian logic and atomism: an exposition of the Nyāya and Vaiçeṣika systems, Greenwood Press, Template:Oclc
- Bimal Matilal (1977), A History of Indian Literature – Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika, Otto Harrassowitz Verlag, Template:ISBN, Template:Oclc
- Stephen Phillips (2012), Epistemology in classical India: the knowledge sources of the Nyāya school, Routledge, Template:ISBN, Template:Oclc
- Karl Potter (1977), Indian metaphysics and epistemology: the tradition of Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika up to Gaṅgeśa, Princeton University Press, Template:Oclc
Navya-Nyaya school
[edit]- Bimal Matilal, The Navya-nyāya doctrine of negation: the semantics and ontology of negative statements, Harvard University Press, Template:Oclc
- Daniel H.H. Ingalls, Materials for the study of Navya-nyāya logic, Harvard University Press, Template:Oclc
External links
[edit]- Template:Cite SEP
- Template:Cite SEP
- Template:Cite IEP
- Lectures on Nyaya Template:Webarchive The Oxford Centre for Hindu Studies, Oxford University
- Ganeri, Jonardon, Edward N. Zalta (ed.), "Analytic Philosophy in Early Modern India", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Template:Hindudharma Template:Indian Philosophy Template:Philosophy topics Template:Logic