Borel–Cantelli lemma
Template:Short description Template:More footnotes In probability theory, the Borel–Cantelli lemma is a theorem about sequences of events. In general, it is a result in measure theory. It is named after Émile Borel and Francesco Paolo Cantelli, who gave statement to the lemma in the first decades of the 20th century.<ref>E. Borel, "Les probabilités dénombrables et leurs applications arithmetiques" Rend. Circ. Mat. Palermo (2) 27 (1909) pp. 247–271.</ref><ref>F.P. Cantelli, "Sulla probabilità come limite della frequenza", Atti Accad. Naz. Lincei 26:1 (1917) pp.39–45.</ref> A related result, sometimes called the second Borel–Cantelli lemma, is a partial converse of the first Borel–Cantelli lemma. The lemma states that, under certain conditions, an event will have probability of either zero or one. Accordingly, it is the best-known of a class of similar theorems, known as zero-one laws. Other examples include Kolmogorov's zero–one law and the Hewitt–Savage zero–one law.
Statement of lemma for probability spaces
[edit]Let E1, E2, ... be a sequence of events in some probability space. The Borel–Cantelli lemma states:<ref>Template:Cite book</ref><ref name=":0">Template:Cite book</ref>
Here, "lim sup" denotes limit supremum of the sequence of events. That is, lim sup En is the outcome that infinitely many of the infinite sequence of events (En) actually occur. Explicitly, <math display="block">\limsup_{n\to\infty} E_n = \bigcap_{n=1}^\infty \bigcup_{k = n}^\infty E_k.</math>The set lim sup En is sometimes denoted {En i.o.}, where "i.o." stands for "infinitely often". The theorem therefore asserts that if the sum of the probabilities of the events En is finite, then the set of all outcomes that contain infinitely many events must have probability zero. Note that no assumption of independence is required.
Example
[edit]Suppose (Xn) is a sequence of random variables with Pr(Xn = 0) = 1/n2 for each n. The probability that Xn = 0 occurs for infinitely many n is equivalent to the probability of the intersection of infinitely many [Xn = 0] events. The intersection of infinitely many such events is a set of outcomes common to all of them. However, the sum ΣPr(Xn = 0) converges to Template:Nowrap and so the Borel–Cantelli Lemma states that the set of outcomes that are common to infinitely many such events occurs with probability zero. Hence, the probability of Xn = 0 occurring for infinitely many n is 0. Almost surely (i.e., with probability 1), Xn is nonzero for all but finitely many n.
Proof
[edit]Let (En) be a sequence of events in some probability space.
The sequence of events <math display="inline">\left\{\bigcup_{n=N}^\infty E_n\right\}^\infty_{N=1}</math> is non-increasing: <math display="block">\bigcup_{n=1}^\infty E_n \supseteq \bigcup_{n=2}^\infty E_n \supseteq \cdots \supseteq \bigcup_{n=N}^\infty E_n \supseteq \bigcup_{n=N+1}^\infty E_n \supseteq \cdots \supseteq \limsup_{n\to\infty} E_n.</math>By continuity from above, <math display="block">\Pr(\limsup_{n \to \infty} E_n) = \lim_{N\to\infty}\Pr\left(\bigcup_{n=N}^\infty E_n\right).</math>By subadditivity, <math display="block">\Pr\left(\bigcup_{n=N}^\infty E_n\right) \leq \sum^\infty_{n=N} \Pr(E_n).</math>By original assumption, <math display="inline">\sum_{n=1}^\infty \Pr(E_n)<\infty.</math> As the series <math display="inline"> \sum_{n=1}^\infty \Pr(E_n)</math> converges, <math display="block">\lim_{N\to\infty} \sum^\infty_{n=N} \Pr(E_n)=0,</math> as required.<ref name="math.ucdavis.edu">Template:Cite web</ref>
General measure spaces
[edit]For general measure spaces, the Borel–Cantelli lemma takes the following form:
Converse result
[edit]A related result, sometimes called the second Borel–Cantelli lemma, is a partial converse of the first Borel–Cantelli lemma. The lemma states: If the events En are independent and the sum of the probabilities of the En diverges to infinity, then the probability that infinitely many of them occur is 1. That is:<ref name=":0" />
The assumption of independence can be weakened to pairwise independence, but in that case the proof is more difficult.
The infinite monkey theorem follows from this second lemma.
Example
[edit]The lemma can be applied to give a covering theorem in Rn. Specifically Template:Harv, if Ej is a collection of Lebesgue measurable subsets of a compact set in Rn such that <math display="block">\sum_j \mu(E_j) = \infty,</math> then there is a sequence Fj of translates <math display="block">F_j = E_j + x_j </math> such that <math display="block">\lim\sup F_j = \bigcap_{n=1}^\infty \bigcup_{k=n}^\infty F_k = \mathbb{R}^n</math> apart from a set of measure zero.
Proof
[edit]Suppose that <math display="inline">\sum_{n = 1}^\infty \Pr(E_n) = \infty</math> and the events <math>(E_n)^\infty_{n = 1}</math> are independent. It is sufficient to show the event that the En's did not occur for infinitely many values of n has probability 0. This is just to say that it is sufficient to show that <math display="block"> 1-\Pr(\limsup_{n \to \infty} E_n) = 0. </math>
Noting that: <math display="block">\begin{align} 1 - \Pr(\limsup_{n \to \infty} E_n) &= 1 - \Pr\left(\{E_n\text{ i.o.}\}\right) = \Pr\left(\{E_n \text{ i.o.}\}^c \right) \\ & = \Pr\left(\left(\bigcap_{N=1}^\infty \bigcup_{n=N}^\infty E_n\right)^c \right) = \Pr\left(\bigcup_{N=1}^\infty \bigcap_{n=N}^\infty E_n^c \right)\\ &= \Pr\left(\liminf_{n \to \infty}E_n^{c}\right)= \lim_{N \to \infty}\Pr\left(\bigcap_{n=N}^\infty E_n^c \right), \end{align} </math> it is enough to show: <math display="inline">\Pr\left(\bigcap_{n=N}^{\infty} E_n^{c}\right) = 0</math>. Since the <math>(E_n)^{\infty}_{n = 1}</math> are independent: <math display="block">\begin{align} \Pr\left(\bigcap_{n=N}^\infty E_n^c\right) &= \prod^\infty_{n=N} \Pr(E_n^c) \\ &= \prod^\infty_{n=N} (1-\Pr(E_n)). \end{align} </math> The convergence test for infinite products guarantees that the product above is 0, if <math display="inline">\sum_{n = N}^\infty \Pr(E_n)</math> diverges. This completes the proof.
Counterpart
[edit]Another related result is the so-called counterpart of the Borel–Cantelli lemma. It is a counterpart of the Lemma in the sense that it gives a necessary and sufficient condition for the limsup to be 1 by replacing the independence assumption by the completely different assumption that <math>(A_n)</math> is monotone increasing for sufficiently large indices. This Lemma says:
Let <math>(A_n)</math> be such that <math>A_k \subseteq A_{k+1}</math>, and let <math>\bar A</math> denote the complement of <math>A</math>. Then the probability of infinitely many <math>A_k</math> occur (that is, at least one <math>A_k</math> occurs) is one if and only if there exists a strictly increasing sequence of positive integers <math>( t_k)</math> such that <math display="block"> \sum_k \Pr( A_{t_{k+1}} \mid \bar A_{t_k}) = \infty. </math>This simple result can be useful in problems such as for instance those involving hitting probabilities for stochastic process with the choice of the sequence <math>(t_k)</math> usually being the essence.
Kochen–Stone
[edit]Let <math>(A_n)</math> be a sequence of events with <math display="inline">\sum\Pr(A_n)=\infty</math> and <math display="inline"> \limsup_{k\to\infty} \frac{\left(\sum_{n=1}^k\Pr(A_n)\right)^2} {\sum_{1\le m,n \le k} \Pr(A_m\cap A_n)} > 0.</math> Then there is a positive probability that <math>A_n</math> occur infinitely often.
Proof
[edit]Let <math> S_{m,n} = \sum^n_{i=m} \mathbf{1}_{A_i}</math>. Then, note that <math display="block"> E[S_{m,n}]^2 = \left(\sum^n_{i=m} \Pr(A_i)\right)^2 </math> and <math display="block"> E[S_{m,n}^2] = \sum_{1\le i \le j\le n} \Pr(A_i\cap A_j). </math> Hence, we know that <math> \limsup_{n\to\infty} \frac{\mathbb{E}[S_{1,n}]^2}{\mathbb{E}[S_{1,n}^2]} > 0.</math> We have that <math display="block> \Pr\left(\bigcup^n_{i=m} A_i\right) = \Pr(S_{m,n} > 0). </math> Now, notice that by the Cauchy-Schwarz Inequality, <math display="block"> \mathbb{E}[X]^2 \le \mathbb{E}[X\mathbf{1}_{\{X>0\}}]^2 \le \mathbb{E}[X^2]\Pr(X>0), </math> therefore, <math display="block"> \Pr(S_{m,n} > 0) \ge \frac{\mathbb{E}[S_{m,n}]^2}{\mathbb{E}[S_{m,n}^2]}. </math> We then have <math display="block"> \frac{\mathbb{E}[S_{m,n}]^2}{\mathbb{E}[S_{m,n}^2]} \ge \frac{E[S_{1,n} - S_{1,m-1}]^2}{E[S_{1,n}^2]}. </math> Given <math> m </math>, since <math> \lim_{n\to\infty} \mathbb{E}[S_{1,n}] = \infty </math>, we can find <math> n </math> large enough so that <math display="block"> \biggr|\frac{\mathbb{E}[S_{1,n}]-\mathbb{E}[S_{1,m-1}]}{\mathbb{E}[S_{1,n}]} - 1\biggr| < \epsilon, </math> for any given <math> \epsilon > 0 </math>. Therefore, <math display="block"> \lim_{m\to\infty}\sup_{n\ge m}\Pr\left(\bigcup_{i=m}^n A_i\right) \ge \lim_{m\to\infty}\sup_{n\ge m}\frac{E[S_{1,n}]^2}{E[S_{1,n}^2]} > 0. </math> But the left side is precisely the probability that the <math> A_n </math> occur infinitely often since <math> \{A_k \text{ i.o.}\} = \{\omega\in\Omega : \forall m, \exists n\ge m \text{ s.t. } \omega\in A_n\}. </math> We're done now, since we've shown that <math> P(A_k \text{ i.o.}) > 0.</math>
See also
[edit]References
[edit]- Template:Springer
- Template:Citation.
- Template:Citation.
- Template:Citation.
- Durrett, Rick. "Probability: Theory and Examples." Duxbury advanced series, Third Edition, Thomson Brooks/Cole, 2005.
External links
[edit]- Planet Math Proof Refer for a simple proof of the Borel Cantelli Lemma