Epicurus
Template:Short description Template:Distinguish Template:Good article Template:Use dmy dates Template:Infobox philosopher
Epicurus (Template:IPAc-en, Template:Respell;<ref name=jones/> Template:Langx Template:Transliteration; 341–270 BC) was an ancient Greek philosopher who founded Epicureanism, a highly influential school of philosophy that asserted that philosophy's purpose is to attain as well as to help others attain tranquil lives, characterized by freedom from fear and the absence of pain.
Epicurus advocated that people were best able to pursue philosophy by living a self-sufficient life surrounded by friends; he and his followers were known for eating simple meals and discussing a wide range of philosophical subjects at "the Garden", the school he established in Athens. Epicurus taught that although the gods exist, they have no involvement in human affairs. Like the earlier philosopher Democritus, Epicurus claimed that all occurrences in the natural world are ultimately the result of tiny, invisible particles known as atoms moving and interacting in empty space, though Epicurus also deviated from Democritus by proposing the idea of atomic "swerve", which holds that atoms may deviate from their expected course, thus permitting humans to possess free will in an otherwise deterministic universe.
Of the over 300 works said to have been written by Epicurus about various subjects, the vast majority have been lost. Only three letters written by him—the letters to Menoeceus, Pythocles, and Herodotus—and two collections of quotes—the Principal Doctrines and the Vatican Sayings—have survived intact, along with a few fragments of his other writings; most knowledge about his philosophy is due to later authors.
Epicureanism reached the height of its popularity during the late years of the Roman Republic, but by late antiquity, it had died out. Throughout the Middle Ages, Epicurus was popularly, though inaccurately, remembered as a patron of drunkards, whoremongers, and gluttons. His teachings gradually became more widely known in the fifteenth century with the rediscovery of important texts, but his ideas did not become acceptable until the seventeenth century, when the French Catholic priest Pierre Gassendi revived a modified version of them, which was promoted by other writers, including Walter Charleton and Robert Boyle. His influence grew considerably during and after the Enlightenment, profoundly impacting the ideas of major thinkers, including John Locke, Thomas Jefferson, Jeremy Bentham, and Karl Marx.
Life
[edit]Upbringing and influences
[edit]Epicurus was born in the Athenian settlement on the Aegean island of Samos in February 341 BC.<ref name=laerti2/>Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn His parents, Neocles and Chaerestrate, were both Athenian-born, and his father was an Athenian citizen.<ref name=laerti2/> Epicurus grew up during the final years of the Greek Classical Period.Template:Sfn Plato had died seven years before Epicurus was born and Epicurus was seven years old when Alexander the Great crossed the Hellespont into Persia.Template:Sfn As a child, Epicurus would have received a typical ancient Greek education.Template:Sfn As such, according to Norman Wentworth DeWitt, "it is inconceivable that he would have escaped the Platonic training in geometry, dialectic, and rhetoric."Template:Sfn Epicurus is known to have studied under the instruction of a Samian Platonist named Pamphilus, probably for about four years.Template:Sfn His Letter of Menoeceus and surviving fragments of his other writings strongly suggest that he had extensive training in rhetoric.Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn After the death of Alexander the Great, Perdiccas expelled the Athenian settlers on Samos to Colophon, on the coast of what is now Turkey.<ref name=stanf/>Template:Sfn Epicurus joined his family there after the completion of his military service. He studied under Nausiphanes, who followed the teachings of Democritus,Template:Sfn<ref name=stanf/> and later those of Pyrrho,<ref>Diogenes Laertius, ix.</ref><ref>Sextus Empiricus, adv. Math. i. 1.</ref> whose way of life Epicurus greatly admired.<ref>Template:Cite book</ref>
Epicurus's teachings were heavily influenced by those of earlier philosophers, particularly Democritus. Nonetheless, Epicurus differed from his predecessors on several key points of determinism and vehemently denied having been influenced by any previous philosophers, whom he denounced as "confused". Instead, he insisted that he had been "self-taught".<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn According to DeWitt, Epicurus's teachings also show influences from the contemporary philosophical school of Cynicism.Template:Sfn The Cynic philosopher Diogenes of Sinope was still alive when Epicurus would have been in Athens for his required military training and it is possible they may have met.Template:Sfn Diogenes's pupil Crates of Thebes (Template:Circa 365 – Template:Circa 285 BC) was a close contemporary of Epicurus.Template:Sfn Epicurus agreed with the Cynics' quest for honesty, but rejected their "insolence and vulgarity", instead teaching that honesty must be coupled with courtesy and kindness.Template:Sfn Epicurus shared this view with his contemporary, the comic playwright Menander.Template:Sfn
Epicurus's Letter to Menoeceus, possibly an early work of his, is written in an eloquent style similar to that of the Athenian rhetorician Isocrates (436–338 BC),Template:Sfn but, for his later works, he seems to have adopted the bald, intellectual style of the mathematician Euclid.Template:Sfn Epicurus's epistemology also bears an unacknowledged debt to the later writings of Aristotle (384–322 BC), who rejected the Platonic idea of hypostatic Reason and instead relied on nature and empirical evidence for knowledge about the universe.Template:Sfn During Epicurus's formative years, Greek knowledge about the rest of the world was rapidly expanding due to the Hellenization of the Near East and the rise of Hellenistic kingdoms.Template:Sfn Epicurus's philosophy was consequently more universal in its outlook than those of his predecessors, since it took cognizance of non-Greek peoples as well as Greeks.Template:Sfn He may have had access to the now-lost writings of the historian and ethnographer Megasthenes, who wrote during the reign of Seleucus I Nicator (ruled 305–281 BC).Template:Sfn
Teaching career
[edit]During Epicurus's lifetime, Platonism was the dominant philosophy in higher education.Template:Sfn Epicurus's opposition to Platonism formed a large part of his thought.Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn Over half of the forty Principal Doctrines of Epicureanism are flat contradictions of Platonism.Template:Sfn In around 311 BC, Epicurus, when he was around thirty years old, began teaching in Mytilene.Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn Around this time, Zeno of Citium, the founder of Stoicism, arrived in Athens, at the age of about twenty-one, but Zeno did not begin teaching what would become Stoicism for another twenty years.Template:Sfn Although later texts, such as the writings of the first-century BC Roman orator Cicero, portray Epicureanism and Stoicism as rivals,Template:Sfn this rivalry seems to have only emerged after Epicurus's death.Template:Sfn
Epicurus's teachings caused strife in Mytilene and he was forced to leave. He then founded a school in Lampsacus before returning to Athens in Template:Circa 306 BC, where he remained until his death.Template:Sfn There he founded The Garden (κῆπος), a school named for the garden he owned that served as the school's meeting place, about halfway between the locations of two other schools of philosophy, the Stoa and the Academy.<ref name="Stanford">Template:Cite encyclopedia</ref>Template:Sfn The Garden was more than just a school;Template:Sfn it was "a community of like-minded and aspiring practitioners of a particular way of life."Template:Sfn The primary members were Hermarchus, the financier Idomeneus, Leonteus and his wife Themista, the satirist Colotes, the mathematician Polyaenus of Lampsacus, and Metrodorus of Lampsacus, the most famous popularizer of Epicureanism. His school was the first of the ancient Greek philosophical schools to admit women as a rule rather than an exception,Template:Citation needed and the biography of Epicurus by Diogenes Laërtius lists female students such as Leontion and Nikidion.<ref>Diogenes Laërtius, Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Book X, Section 7</ref> An inscription on the gate to The Garden is recorded by Seneca the Younger in epistle XXI of Template:Lang: "Stranger, here you will do well to tarry; here our highest good is pleasure."<ref name=intra/>
According to Diskin Clay, Epicurus himself established a custom of celebrating his birthday annually with common meals, befitting his stature as heros ktistes ("founding hero") of the Garden. He ordained in his will annual memorial feasts for himself on the same date (10th of Gamelion month).<ref name=smitwood/> Epicurean communities continued this tradition,<ref name=glad/> referring to Epicurus as their "saviour" (soter) and celebrating him as hero. The hero cult of Epicurus may have operated as a Garden variety civic religion.<ref name=nussb/> However, clear evidence of an Epicurean hero cult, as well as the cult itself, seems buried by the weight of posthumous philosophical interpretation.<ref name=clay/> Epicurus never married and had no known children. He was most likely a vegetarian.<ref name=brita/><ref name=dombr/>
Death
[edit]Diogenes Laërtius records that, according to Epicurus's successor Hermarchus, Epicurus died a slow and painful death in 270 BC at the age of seventy-two from a stone blockage of his urinary tract.<ref name="bitsori" /><ref name=laerti3/>Template:Bsn Despite being in immense pain, Epicurus is said to have remained cheerful and to have continued to teach until the very end.<ref name="bitsori" />Template:Bsn Possible insights into Epicurus's death may be offered by the extremely brief Epistle to Idomeneus, included by Diogenes Laërtius in Book X of his Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers.Template:Sfn The authenticity of this letter is uncertain and it may be a later pro-Epicurean forgery intended to paint an admirable portrait of the philosopher to counter the large number of forged epistles in Epicurus's name portraying him unfavorably.Template:Sfn
I have written this letter to you on a happy day to me, which is also the last day of my life. For I have been attacked by a painful inability to urinate, and also dysentery, so violent that nothing can be added to the violence of my sufferings. But the cheerfulness of my mind, which comes from the recollection of all my philosophical contemplation, counterbalances all these afflictions. And I beg you to take care of the children of Metrodorus, in a manner worthy of the devotion shown by the young man to me, and to philosophy.<ref name=laerti4>Diogenes Laërtius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers, 10.22 (trans. C.D. Yonge).</ref>
If authentic, this letter would support the tradition that Epicurus was able to remain joyful to the end, even in the midst of his suffering.Template:Sfn It would also indicate that he maintained a special concern for the wellbeing of children.Template:Sfn
Philosophy
[edit]Epistemology
[edit]Epicurus and his followers had a well-developed epistemology, which developed as a result of their rivalry with other philosophical schools.Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn Epicurus wrote a treatise entitled Template:Lang, or Rule, in which he explained his methods of investigation and theory of knowledge.Template:Sfn This book, however, has not survived,Template:Sfn nor does any other text that fully and clearly explains Epicurean epistemology, leaving only mentions of this epistemology by several authors to reconstruct it.Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn Epicurus rejected the Platonic idea of "Reason" as a reliable source of knowledge about the world apart from the sensesTemplate:Sfn and was bitterly opposed to the Pyrrhonists and Academic Skeptics, who not only questioned the ability of the senses to provide accurate knowledge about the world, but also whether it is even possible to know anything about the world at all.Template:Sfn
Epicurus maintained that the senses never deceive humans, but that the senses can be misinterpreted.Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn Epicurus held that the purpose of all knowledge is to aid humans in attaining ataraxia.Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn He taught that knowledge is learned through experiences rather than innateTemplate:Sfn and that the acceptance of the fundamental truth of the things a person perceives is essential to a person's moral and spiritual health.Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn In the Letter to Pythocles, he states, "If a person fights the clear evidence of his senses he will never be able to share in genuine tranquility."Template:Sfn Epicurus regarded gut feelings as the ultimate authority on matters of morality and held that whether a person feels an action is right or wrong is a far more cogent guide to whether that act really is right or wrong than abstracts maxims, strict codified rules of ethics, or even reason itself.Template:Sfn
Epicurus believed that any statement that is not directly contrary to human perception can be considered possibly true.Template:Sfn On the other hand, anything contrary to experience can be ruled out as false.Template:Sfn Epicureans often used analogies to everyday experience to support their argument of so-called "imperceptibles", which included anything that a human being cannot perceive, such as the motion of atoms.Template:Sfn In line with this principle of non-contradiction, the Epicureans believed that events in the natural world may have multiple causes that are all equally possible and probable.Template:Sfn Lucretius writes in On the Nature of Things, as translated by William Ellery Leonard:
<poem>There be, besides, some thing
Of which 'tis not enough one only cause To state—but rather several, whereof one Will be the true: lo, if thou shouldst espy Lying afar some fellow's lifeless corse, 'Twere meet to name all causes of a death, That cause of his death might thereby be named: For prove thou mayst he perished not by steel, By cold, nor even by poison nor disease, Yet somewhat of this sort hath come to him We know—And thus we have to say the same In divers cases.<ref>Template:Cite book
Book VI, Section Extraordinary and Paradoxical Telluric Phenomena, Line 9549–9560</ref></poem>
Epicurus strongly favored naturalistic explanations over theological ones.Template:Sfn In his Letter to Pythocles, he offers four different possible natural explanations for thunder, six different possible natural explanations for lightning, three for snow, three for comets, two for rainbows, two for earthquakes, and so on.Template:Sfn Although all of these explanations are now known to be false, they were an important step in the history of science, because Epicurus was trying to explain natural phenomena using natural explanations, rather than resorting to inventing elaborate stories about gods and mythic heroes.Template:Sfn
Ethics
[edit]Epicurus was a hedonist, meaning he taught that what is pleasurable is morally good and what is painful is morally evil.Template:SfnTemplate:SfnTemplate:SfnTemplate:Sfn He idiosyncratically defined "pleasure" as the absence of sufferingTemplate:SfnTemplate:Sfn and taught that all humans should seek to attain the state of ataraxia, meaning "untroubledness", a state in which the person is completely free from all pain or suffering.Template:Sfn<ref name=folse/><ref name=konstan/> He argued that most of the suffering which human beings experience is caused by the irrational fears of death, divine retribution, and punishment in the afterlife.Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn In his Letter to Menoeceus, Epicurus explains that people seek wealth and power on account of these fears, believing that having more money, prestige, or political clout will save them from death.Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn He, however, maintains that death is the end of existence, that the terrifying stories of punishment in the afterlife are ridiculous superstitions, and that death is therefore nothing to be feared.Template:SfnTemplate:SfnTemplate:Sfn He writes in his Letter to Menoeceus: "Accustom thyself to believe that death is nothing to us, for good and evil imply sentience, and death is the privation of all sentience;... Death, therefore, the most awful of evils, is nothing to us, seeing that, when we are, death is not come, and, when death is come, we are not."Template:Sfn From this doctrine arose the Epicurean epitaph: Non fui, fui, non-sum, non-curo ("I was not; I was; I am not; I do not care"), which is inscribed on the gravestones of his followers and seen on many ancient gravestones of the Roman Empire. This quotation is often used today at humanist funerals.<ref name=humanism>Template:Cite web</ref>
The Tetrapharmakos presents a summary of the key points of Epicurean ethics:<ref>Template:Cite book</ref>
- Don't fear god
- Don't worry about death
- What is good is easy to get
- What is terrible is easy to endure
Although Epicurus has been commonly misunderstood as an advocate of the rampant pursuit of pleasure, he, in fact, maintained that a person can only be happy and free from suffering by living wisely, soberly, and morally.Template:SfnTemplate:SfnTemplate:Sfn He strongly disapproved of raw, excessive sensuality and warned that a person must take into account whether the consequences of his actions will result in suffering,Template:SfnTemplate:SfnTemplate:SfnTemplate:Sfn writing, "the pleasant life is produced not by a string of drinking bouts and revelries, nor by the enjoyment of boys and women, nor by fish and the other items on an expensive menu, but by sober reasoning."Template:Sfn He also wrote that a single good piece of cheese could be equally pleasing as an entire feast.Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn Furthermore, Epicurus taught that "it is not possible to live pleasurably without living sensibly and nobly and justly", because a person who engages in acts of dishonesty or injustice will be "loaded with troubles" on account of his own guilty conscience and will live in constant fear that his wrongdoings will be discovered by others.Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn<ref name=classics/> A person who is kind and just to others, however, will have no fear and will be more likely to attain ataraxia.Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn
Epicurus distinguished between two different types of pleasure: "moving" pleasures (κατὰ κίνησιν ἡδοναί) and "static" pleasures (καταστηματικαὶ ἡδοναί).<ref name=IEP>Template:Cite web</ref><ref name=laerti>Diogenes Laërtius, The Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers, X:136.</ref> "Moving" pleasures occur when one is in the process of satisfying a desire and involve an active titillation of the senses.<ref name=IEP/> After one's desires have been satisfied (e.g. when one is full after eating), the pleasure quickly goes away and the suffering of wanting to fulfill the desire again returns.<ref name=IEP/>Template:Sfn For Epicurus, static pleasures are the best pleasures because moving pleasures are always bound up with pain.<ref name=IEP/>Template:Sfn Epicurus had a low opinion of sex and marriage, regarding both as having dubious value.Template:Sfn Instead, he maintained that platonic friendships are essential to living a happy life.Template:Sfn One of the Principal Doctrines states, "Of the things wisdom acquires for the blessedness of life as a whole, far the greatest is the possession of friendship."<ref>Epicurus, Principal Doctrines 27</ref>Template:Sfn He also taught that philosophy is itself a pleasure to engage in.Template:Sfn One of the quotes from Epicurus recorded in the Vatican Sayings declares, "In other pursuits, the hard-won fruit comes at the end. But in philosophy, delight keeps pace with knowledge. It is not after the lesson that enjoyment comes: learning and enjoyment happen at the same time."<ref>Epicurus, Vatican Sayings 27</ref>Template:Sfn
Epicurus distinguishes between three types of desires: natural and necessary, natural but unnecessary, and vain and empty. Natural and necessary desires include the desires for food and shelter. These are easy to satisfy, difficult to eliminate, bring pleasure when satisfied, and are naturally limited. Going beyond these limits produces unnecessary desires, such as the desire for luxury foods. Although food is necessary, luxury food is not necessary. Correspondingly, Epicurus advocates a life of hedonistic moderation by reducing desire, thus eliminating the unhappiness caused by unfulfilled desires. Vain desires include desires for power, wealth, and fame. These are difficult to satisfy because no matter how much one gets, one can always want more. These desires are inculcated by society and by false beliefs about what we need. They are not natural and are to be shunned.<ref>Template:Cite web</ref>
Epicurus' teachings were introduced into medical philosophy and practice by the Epicurean doctor Asclepiades of Bithynia, who was the first physician who introduced Greek medicine in Rome. Asclepiades introduced the friendly, sympathetic, pleasing and painless treatment of patients. He advocated humane treatment of mental disorders, had insane persons freed from confinement and treated them with natural therapy, such as diet and massages. His teachings are surprisingly modern; therefore Asclepiades is considered to be a pioneer physician in psychotherapy, physical therapy and molecular medicine.<ref name=yapij/>
Physics
[edit]Epicurus writes in his Letter to Herodotus (not the historian)<ref>Template:Cite web</ref> that "nothing ever arises from the nonexistent", indicating that all events therefore have causes, regardless of whether those causes are known or unknown.Template:Sfn Similarly, he also writes that nothing ever passes away into nothingness, because, "if an object that passes from our view were completely annihilated, everything in the world would have perished, since that into which things were dissipated would be nonexistent."Template:Sfn He therefore states: "The totality of things was always just as it is at present and will always remain the same because there is nothing into which it can change, inasmuch as there is nothing outside the totality that could intrude and effect change."Template:Sfn Like Democritus before him, Epicurus taught that all matter is entirely made of extremely tiny particles called "atoms" (Template:Langx; Template:Lang, meaning "indivisible").Template:Sfn For Epicurus and his followers, the existence of atoms was a matter of empirical observation;Template:Sfn Epicurus's devoted follower, the Roman poet Lucretius, cites the gradual wearing down of rings from being worn, statues from being kissed, stones from being dripped on by water, and roads from being walked on in On the Nature of Things as evidence for the existence of atoms as tiny, imperceptible particles.Template:Sfn
Also like Democritus, Epicurus was a materialist who taught that the only things that exist are atoms and void.Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn Void occurs in any place where there are no atoms.Template:Sfn Epicurus and his followers believed that atoms and void are both infinite and that the universe is therefore boundless.Template:Sfn In On the Nature of Things, Lucretius argues this point using the example of a man throwing a javelin at the theoretical boundary of a finite universe.Template:Sfn He states that the javelin must either go past the edge of the universe, in which case it is not really a boundary, or it must be blocked by something and prevented from continuing its path, but, if that happens, then the object blocking it must be outside the confines of the universe.Template:Sfn As a result of this belief that the universe and the number of atoms in it are infinite, Epicurus and the Epicureans believed that there must also be infinitely many worlds within the universe.Template:Sfn
Epicurus taught that the motion of atoms is constant, eternal, and without beginning or end.Template:Sfn He held that there are two kinds of motion: the motion of atoms and the motion of visible objects.Template:Sfn Both kinds of motion are real and not illusory.Template:Sfn Democritus had described atoms as not only eternally moving, but also eternally flying through space, colliding, coalescing, and separating from each other as necessary.Template:Sfn In a rare departure from Democritus's physics, Epicurus posited the idea of atomic "swerve" (Template:Lang Template:Lang; Template:Langx), one of his best-known original ideas.Template:SfnTemplate:Efn According to this idea, atoms, as they are travelling through space, may deviate slightly from the course they would ordinarily be expected to follow.Template:Sfn Epicurus's reason for introducing this doctrine was because he wanted to preserve the concepts of free will and ethical responsibility while still maintaining the deterministic physical model of atomism.Template:Sfn Lucretius describes it, saying, "It is this slight deviation of primal bodies, at indeterminate times and places, which keeps the mind as such from experiencing an inner compulsion in doing everything it does and from being forced to endure and suffer like a captive in chains."Template:Sfn
Epicurus was first to assert human freedom as a result of the fundamental indeterminism in the motion of atoms. This has led some philosophers to think that, for Epicurus, free will was caused directly by chance. In his On the Nature of Things, Lucretius appears to suggest this in the best-known passage on Epicurus' position.<ref name=tufts/> In his Letter to Menoeceus, however, Epicurus follows Aristotle and clearly identifies three possible causes: "some things happen of necessity, others by chance, others through our own agency." Aristotle said some things "depend on us" (eph'hemin). Epicurus agreed, and said it is to these last things that praise and blame naturally attach. For Epicurus, the "swerve" of the atoms simply defeated determinism to leave room for autonomous agency.<ref name=infop/>
Theology
[edit]In his Letter to Menoeceus, a summary of his own moral and theological teachings, the first piece of advice Epicurus himself gives to his student is: "First, believe that a god is an indestructible and blessed animal, in accordance with the general conception of god commonly held, and do not ascribe to god anything foreign to his indestructibility or repugnant to his blessedness."Template:Sfn Epicurus maintained that he and his followers knew that the gods exist because "our knowledge of them is a matter of clear and distinct perception", meaning that people can empirically sense their presences.Template:Sfn He did not mean that people can see the gods as physical objects, but rather that they can see visions of the gods sent from the remote regions of interstellar space in which they actually reside.Template:Sfn According to George K. Strodach, Epicurus could have easily dispensed of the gods entirely without greatly altering his materialist worldview,Template:Sfn but the gods still play one important function in Epicurus's theology as the paragons of moral virtue to be emulated and admired.Template:Sfn
Epicurus rejected the conventional Greek view of the gods as anthropomorphic beings who walked the earth like ordinary people, fathered illegitimate offspring with mortals, and pursued personal feuds.Template:Sfn Instead, he taught that the gods are morally perfect, but detached and immobile beings who live in the remote regions of interstellar space.Template:Sfn In line with these teachings, Epicurus adamantly rejected the idea that deities were involved in human affairs in any way.Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn Epicurus maintained that the gods are so utterly perfect and removed from the world that they are incapable of listening to prayers or supplications or doing virtually anything aside from contemplating their own perfections.Template:Sfn In his Letter to Herodotus, he specifically denies that the gods have any control over natural phenomena, arguing that this would contradict their fundamental nature, which is perfect, because any kind of worldly involvement would tarnish their perfection.Template:Sfn He further warned that believing that the gods control natural phenomena would only mislead people into believing the superstitious view that the gods punish humans for wrongdoing, which only instills fear and prevents people from attaining ataraxia.Template:Sfn
Epicurus himself criticizes popular religion in both his Letter to Menoeceus and his Letter to Herodotus, but in a restrained and moderate tone.Template:Sfn Later Epicureans mainly followed the same ideas as Epicurus, believing in the existence of the gods, but emphatically rejecting the idea of divine providence.Template:Sfn Their criticisms of popular religion, however, are often less gentle than those of Epicurus himself.Template:Sfn The Letter to Pythocles, written by a later Epicurean, is dismissive and contemptuous towards popular religionTemplate:Sfn and Epicurus's devoted follower, the Roman poet Lucretius (Template:Circa 99 BC – Template:Circa 55 BC), passionately assailed popular religion in his philosophical poem On the Nature of Things.Template:Sfn In this poem, Lucretius declares that popular religious practices not only do not instill virtue, but rather result in "misdeeds both wicked and ungodly", citing the mythical sacrifice of Iphigenia as an example.Template:Sfn Lucretius argues that divine creation and providence are illogical, not because the gods do not exist, but rather because these notions are incompatible with the Epicurean principles of the gods' indestructibility and blessedness.Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn The later Pyrrhonist philosopher Sextus Empiricus (Template:Circa 160 – Template:Circa 210 AD) rejected the teachings of the Epicureans specifically because he regarded them as theological "Dogmaticists".Template:Sfn
Politics
[edit]Epicurus promoted an innovative theory of justice as a social contract. Justice, Epicurus said, is an agreement neither to harm nor be harmed, and we need to have such a contract in order to enjoy fully the benefits of living together in a well-ordered society. Laws and punishments are needed to keep misguided fools in line who would otherwise break the contract. But the wise person sees the usefulness of justice, and because of his limited desires, he has no need to engage in the conduct prohibited by the laws in any case. Laws that are useful for promoting happiness are just, but those that are not useful are not just. (Principal Doctrines 31–40)
Epicurus discouraged participation in politics, as doing so leads to perturbation and status seeking. He instead advocated not drawing attention to oneself. This principle is epitomised by the phrase lathe biōsas (Template:Lang), meaning "live in obscurity", "get through life without drawing attention to yourself", i.e., live without pursuing glory or wealth or power, but anonymously, enjoying little things like food, the company of friends, etc. Plutarch elaborated on this theme in his essay Is the Saying "Live in Obscurity" Right? (Template:Lang, An recte dictum sit latenter esse vivendum) 1128c; cf. Flavius Philostratus, Vita Apollonii 8.28.12.<ref>Template:Cite web</ref>
Works
[edit]Epicurus was an extremely prolific writer.Template:SfnTemplate:SfnTemplate:SfnTemplate:Sfn According to Diogenes Laërtius, he wrote around 300 treatises on a variety of subjects.Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn Although more original writings of Epicurus have survived to the present day than of any other Hellenistic Greek philosopher,Template:Sfn the vast majority of everything he wrote has still been lost,Template:SfnTemplate:SfnTemplate:Sfn and most of what is known about Epicurus's teachings come from the writings of his later followers, particularly the Roman poet Lucretius.Template:Sfn The only surviving complete works by Epicurus are three relatively lengthy letters, which are quoted in their entirety in Book X of Diogenes Laërtius's Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers, and two groups of quotes: the Principal Doctrines (Κύριαι Δόξαι), which are likewise preserved through quotation by Diogenes Laërtius, and the Vatican Sayings, preserved in a manuscript from the Vatican Library that was first discovered in 1888.Template:Sfn In the Letter to Herodotus and the Letter to Pythocles, Epicurus summarizes his philosophy on nature and, in the Letter to Menoeceus, he summarizes his moral teachings.Template:Sfn Numerous fragments of Epicurus's lost thirty-seven volume treatise On Nature have been found among the charred papyrus fragments at the Villa of the Papyri at Herculaneum.Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn Scholars first began attempting to unravel and decipher these scrolls in 1800, but the efforts are painstaking and are still ongoing.Template:Sfn According to Diogenes Laertius (10.27-9), the major works of Epicurus include: Template:Refbegin
- On Nature, in 37 books
- On Atoms and the Void
- On Love
- Abridgment of the Arguments employed against the Natural Philosophers
- Against the Megarians
- Problems
- Fundamental Propositions (Kyriai Doxai)
- On Choice and Avoidance
- On the Chief Good
- On the Criterion (the Canon)
- Chaeridemus,
- On the Gods
- On Piety
- Hegesianax
- Four essays on Lives
- Essay on Just Dealing
- Neocles
- Essay addressed to Themista
- The Banquet (Symposium)
- Eurylochus
- Essay addressed to Metrodorus
- Essay on Seeing
- Essay on the Angle in an Atom
- Essay on Touch
- Essay on Fate
- Opinions on the Passions
- Treatise addressed to Timocrates
- Prognostics
- Exhortations
- On Images
- On Perceptions
- Aristobulus
- Essay on Music (i.e., on music, poetry, and dance)
- On Justice and the other Virtues
- On Gifts and Gratitude
- Polymedes
- Timocrates (three books)
- Metrodorus (five books)
- Antidorus (two books)
- Opinions about Diseases and Death, addressed to Mithras
- Callistolas
- Essay on Kingly Power
- Anaximenes
- Letters
Legacy
[edit]Ancient Epicureanism
[edit]Epicureanism was extremely popular from the very beginning,Template:SfnTemplate:SfnTemplate:Sfn and rapidly spread beyond the Greek mainland all across the Mediterranean world.Template:Sfn Epicureans and admirers of Epicureanism revered Epicurus himself as a great teacher of ethics, a savior, and even a god.Template:Sfn His image was worn on finger rings, portraits of him were displayed in living rooms, and wealthy followers venerated likenesses of him in marble sculpture.Template:Sfn His admirers revered his sayings as divine oracles, carried around copies of his writings, and cherished copies of his letters like the letters of an apostle.Template:Sfn On the twentieth day of every month, admirers of his teachings would perform a solemn ritual to honor his memory.Template:Sfn Nonetheless, Epicurus was not universally admired and, within his own lifetime, he was vilified as an ignorant buffoon and egoistic sybarite.Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn The overwhelming majority of surviving Greek and Roman sources are vehemently negative towards EpicureanismTemplate:Sfn and, according to Pamela Gordon, they routinely depict Epicurus himself as "monstrous or laughable".Template:Sfn He remained the most simultaneously admired and despised philosopher in the Mediterranean for the next nearly five centuries.Template:Sfn
By the first century BC, Epicureanism had established a strong foothold in Italy.Template:Sfn The Roman orator Cicero (106 – 43 BC), who deplored Epicurean ethics, lamented, "the Epicureans have taken Italy by storm."Template:Sfn Many Romans in particular took a negative view of Epicureanism, seeing its advocacy of the pursuit of voluptas ("pleasure") as contrary to the Roman ideal of virtus ("manly virtue").Template:Sfn The Romans therefore often stereotyped Epicurus and his followers as weak and effeminate.Template:Sfn Prominent critics of his philosophy include prominent authors such as the Roman Stoic Seneca the Younger (Template:Circa 4 BC – AD 65) and the Greek Middle Platonist Plutarch (Template:Circa 46 – Template:Circa 120), who both derided these stereotypes as immoral and disreputable.Template:Sfn Gordon characterizes anti-Epicurean rhetoric as so "heavy-handed" and misrepresentative of Epicurus's actual teachings that they sometimes come across as "comical".Template:Sfn In his De vita beata, Seneca states that the "sect of Epicurus... has a bad reputation, and yet it does not deserve it." and compares it to "a man in a dress: your chastity remains, your virility is unimpaired, your body has not submitted sexually, but in your hand is a tympanum."<ref>Template:Cite book</ref>
Epicureanism was a notoriously conservative philosophical school;Template:SfnTemplate:SfnTemplate:Sfn although Epicurus's later followers did expand on his philosophy, they dogmatically retained what he himself had originally taught without modifying it.Template:SfnTemplate:SfnTemplate:Sfn In the first and second centuries AD, Epicureanism gradually began to decline as it failed to compete with Stoicism, which had an ethical system more in line with traditional Roman values.Template:Sfn Epicureanism also suffered decay in the wake of Christianity, which was also rapidly expanding throughout the Roman Empire.Template:Sfn Of all the Greek philosophical schools, Epicureanism was the one most at odds with the new Christian teachings, since Epicureans believed that the soul was mortal, denied the existence of an afterlife, denied that the divine had any active role in human life, and advocated pleasure as the foremost goal of human existence.Template:Sfn As such, Christian writers such as Justin Martyr (Template:Circa 100–Template:Circa 165 AD), Athenagoras of Athens (Template:Circa 133–Template:Circa 190), Tertullian (Template:Circa 155–Template:Circa 240), and Clement of Alexandria (Template:Circa 150–Template:Circa 215), Arnobius (died Template:Circa 330), and Lactantius (c. 250-c.325) all singled it out for the most vitriolic criticism.Template:Sfn In spite of this, DeWitt argues that Epicureanism and Christianity share much common language, calling Epicureanism "the first missionary philosophy" and "the first world philosophy".Template:Sfn Both Epicureanism and Christianity placed strong emphasis on the importance of love and forgivenessTemplate:Sfn and early Christian portrayals of Jesus are often similar to Epicurean portrayals of Epicurus.Template:Sfn DeWitt argues that Epicureanism, in many ways, helped pave the way for the spread of Christianity by "helping to bridge the gap between Greek intellectualism and a religious way of life" and "shunt[ing] the emphasis from the political to the social virtues and offer[ing] what may be called a religion of humanity."Template:Sfn
Epicurean paradox
[edit]Template:See also Template:Theodicy The Epicurean paradox or riddle of Epicurus or Epicurus' trilemma is a version of the problem of evil. Lactantius attributes this trilemma to Epicurus in De Ira Dei, 13, 20-21:
God, he says, either wishes to take away evils, and is unable; or He is able, and is unwilling; or He is neither willing nor able, or He is both willing and able. If He is willing and is unable, He is feeble, which is not in accordance with the character of God; if He is able and unwilling, He is envious, which is equally at variance with God; if He is neither willing nor able, He is both envious and feeble, and therefore not God; if He is both willing and able, which alone is suitable to God, from what source then are evils? Or why does He not remove them?
In Dialogues concerning Natural Religion (1779), David Hume also attributes the argument to Epicurus:
Epicurus’s old questions are yet unanswered. Is he willing to prevent evil, but not able? then is he impotent. Is he able, but not willing? then is he malevolent. Is he both able and willing? whence then is evil?
No extant writings of Epicurus contain this argument.Template:Sfn However, the vast majority of Epicurus's writings have been lost and it is possible that some form of this argument may have been found in his lost treatise On the Gods, which Diogenes Laërtius describes as one of his greatest works.Template:Sfn If Epicurus really did make some form of this argument, it would not have been an argument against the existence of deities, but rather an argument against divine providence.Template:Sfn Epicurus's extant writings demonstrate that he did believe in the existence of deities.Template:Sfn Furthermore, religion was such an integral part of daily life in Greece during the early Hellenistic Period that it is doubtful anyone during that period could have been an atheist in the modern sense of the word.Template:Sfn Instead, the Greek word Template:Lang (átheos), meaning "without a god", was used as a term of abuse, not as an attempt to describe a person's beliefs.Template:Sfn
Middle Ages
[edit]By the early fifth century AD, Epicureanism was virtually extinct.Template:Sfn The Christian Church Father Augustine of Hippo (354–430 AD) declared, "its ashes are so cold that not a single spark can be struck from them."Template:Sfn While the ideas of Plato and Aristotle could easily be adapted to suit a Christian worldview, the ideas of Epicurus were not nearly as easily amenable.Template:Sfn As such, while Plato and Aristotle enjoyed a privileged place in Christian philosophy throughout the Middle Ages, Epicurus was not held in such esteem.Template:Sfn Information about Epicurus's teachings was available, through Lucretius's On the Nature of Things, quotations of it found in medieval Latin grammars and florilegia and encyclopedias, such as Isidore of Seville's Etymologiae (seventh century) and Hrabanus Maurus's De universo (ninth century),Template:Sfn but there is little evidence that these teachings were systematically studied or comprehended.Template:Sfn
During the Middle Ages, Epicurus was remembered by the educated as a philosopher,Template:Sfn but he frequently appeared in popular culture as a gatekeeper to the Garden of Delights, the "proprietor of the kitchen, the tavern, and the brothel."Template:Sfn He appears in this guise in Martianus Capella's Marriage of Mercury and Philology (fifth century), John of Salisbury's Policraticus (1159), John Gower's Mirour de l'Omme, and Geoffrey Chaucer's Canterbury Tales.Template:Sfn Epicurus and his followers appear in Dante Alighieri's Inferno in the Sixth Circle of Hell, where they are imprisoned in flaming coffins for having believed that the soul dies with the body.Template:Sfn
Renaissance
[edit]In 1417, a manuscript-hunter named Poggio Bracciolini discovered a copy of Lucretius's On the Nature of Things in a monastery near Lake Constance.Template:Sfn The discovery of this manuscript was met with immense excitement, because scholars were eager to analyze and study the teachings of classical philosophers and this previously forgotten text contained the most comprehensive account of Epicurus's teachings known in Latin.Template:Sfn The first scholarly dissertation on Epicurus, De voluptate (On Pleasure) by the Italian Humanist and Catholic priest Lorenzo Valla was published in 1431.Template:Sfn Valla made no mention of Lucretius or his poem.Template:Sfn Instead, he presented the treatise as a discussion on the nature of the highest good between an Epicurean, a Stoic, and a Christian.Template:Sfn Valla's dialogue ultimately rejects Epicureanism,Template:Sfn but, by presenting an Epicurean as a member of the dispute, Valla lent Epicureanism credibility as a philosophy that deserved to be taken seriously.Template:Sfn
None of the Quattrocento Humanists ever clearly endorsed Epicureanism,Template:Sfn but scholars such as Francesco Zabarella (1360–1417), Francesco Filelfo (1398–1481), Cristoforo Landino (1424–1498), and Leonardo Bruni (Template:Circa 1370–1444) did give Epicureanism a fairer analysis than it had traditionally received and provided a less overtly hostile assessment of Epicurus himself.Template:Sfn Nonetheless, "Epicureanism" remained a pejorative, synonymous with extreme egoistic pleasure-seeking, rather than a name of a philosophical school.Template:Sfn This reputation discouraged orthodox Christian scholars from taking what others might regard as an inappropriately keen interest in Epicurean teachings.Template:Sfn Epicureanism did not take hold in Italy, France, or England until the seventeenth century.Template:Sfn Even the liberal religious skeptics who might have been expected to take an interest in Epicureanism evidently did not;Template:Sfn Étienne Dolet (1509–1546) only mentions Epicurus once in all his writings and François Rabelais (between 1483 and 1494–1553) never mentions him at all.Template:Sfn Michel de Montaigne (1533–1592) is the exception to this trend, quoting a full 450 lines of Lucretius's On the Nature of Things in his Essays.Template:Sfn His interest in Lucretius, however, seems to have been primarily literary and he is ambiguous about his feelings on Lucretius's Epicurean worldview.Template:Sfn During the Protestant Reformation, the label "Epicurean" was bandied back and forth as an insult between Protestants and Catholics.Template:Sfn
Revival
[edit]In the seventeenth century, the French Catholic priest and scholar Pierre Gassendi (1592–1655) sought to dislodge Aristotelianism from its position of the highest dogma by presenting Epicureanism as a better and more rational alternative.Template:Sfn In 1647, Gassendi published his book De vita et moribus Epicuri (The Life and Morals of Epicurus), a passionate defense of Epicureanism.Template:Sfn In 1649, he published a commentary on Diogenes Laërtius's Life of Epicurus.Template:Sfn He left Syntagma philosophicum (Philosophical Compendium), a synthesis of Epicurean doctrines, unfinished at the time of his death in 1655.Template:Sfn It was finally published in 1658, after undergoing revision by his editors.Template:Sfn Gassendi modified Epicurus's teachings to make them palatable for a Christian audience.Template:Sfn For instance, he argued that atoms were not eternal, uncreated, and infinite in number, instead contending that an extremely large but finite number of atoms were created by God at creation.Template:Sfn
As a result of Gassendi's modifications, his books were never censored by the Catholic Church.Template:Sfn They came to exert profound influence on later writings about Epicurus.Template:Sfn Gassendi's version of Epicurus's teachings became popular among some members of English scientific circles.Template:Sfn For these scholars, however, Epicurean atomism was merely a starting point for their own idiosyncratic adaptations of it.Template:Sfn To orthodox thinkers, Epicureanism was still regarded as immoral and heretical.Template:Sfn For instance, Lucy Hutchinson (1620–1681), the first translator of Lucretius's On the Nature of Things into English, railed against Epicurus as "a lunatic dog" who formulated "ridiculous, impious, execrable doctrines".Template:Sfn
Epicurus's teachings were made respectable in England by the natural philosopher Walter Charleton (1619–1707), whose first Epicurean work, The Darkness of Atheism Dispelled by the Light of Nature (1652), advanced Epicureanism as a "new" atomism.Template:Sfn His next work Physiologia Epicuro-Gassendo-Charletoniana, or a Fabrick of Science Natural, upon a Hypothesis of Atoms, Founded by Epicurus, Repaired by Petrus Gassendus, and Augmented by Walter Charleton (1654) emphasized this idea.Template:Sfn These works, together with Charleton's Epicurus's Morals (1658), provided the English public with readily available descriptions of Epicurus's philosophy and assured orthodox Christians that Epicureanism was no threat to their beliefs.Template:Sfn The Royal Society, chartered in 1662, advanced Epicurean atomism.Template:Sfn One of the most prolific defenders of atomism was the chemist Robert Boyle (1627–1691), who argued for it in publications such as The Origins of Forms and Qualities (1666), Experiments, Notes, etc. about the Mechanical Origin and Production of Divers Particular Qualities (1675), and Of the Excellency and Grounds of the Mechanical Hypothesis (1674).Template:Sfn By the end of the seventeenth century, Epicurean atomism was widely accepted by members of the English scientific community as the best model for explaining the physical world,Template:Sfn but it had been modified so greatly that Epicurus was no longer seen as its original parent.Template:Sfn
Enlightenment and after
[edit]The Anglican bishop Joseph Butler's anti-Epicurean polemics in his Fifteen Sermons Preached at the Rolls Chapel (1726) and Analogy of Religion (1736) set the tune for what most orthodox Christians believed about Epicureanism for the remainder of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.Template:Sfn Nonetheless, there are a few indications from this time period of Epicurus's improving reputation.Template:Sfn Epicureanism was beginning to lose its associations with indiscriminate and insatiable gluttony, which had been characteristic of its reputation ever since antiquity.Template:Sfn Instead, the word "epicure" began to refer to a person with extremely refined taste in food.Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn Examples of this usage include "Epicurean cooks / sharpen with cloyless sauce his appetite" from William Shakespeare's Antony and Cleopatra (Act II. scene i; Template:Circa 1607)Template:Sfn and "such an epicure was Potiphar—to please his tooth and pamper his flesh with delicacies" from William Whately's Prototypes (1646).Template:Sfn
Around the same time, the Epicurean injunction to "live in obscurity" was beginning to gain popularity as well.Template:Sfn In 1685, Sir William Temple (1628–1699) abandoned a promising career as a diplomat and instead retired to his garden, devoting himself to writing essays on Epicurus's moral teachings.Template:Sfn That same year, John Dryden translated the celebrated lines from Book II of Lucretius's On the Nature of Things: "'Tis pleasant, safely to behold from shore / The rowling ship, and hear the Tempest roar."Template:Sfn Meanwhile, John Locke (1632–1704) adapted Gassendi's modified version of Epicurus's epistemology, which became highly influential on English empiricism.Template:Sfn Many thinkers with sympathies towards the Enlightenment endorsed Epicureanism as an admirable moral philosophy.Template:Sfn Thomas Jefferson (1743–1826), one of the Founding Fathers of the United States, declared in 1819, "I too am an Epicurean. I consider the genuine (not imputed) doctrines of Epicurus as containing everything rational in moral philosophy which Greece and Rome have left us."Template:Sfn
The German philosopher Karl Marx (1818–1883), whose ideas are the basis of Marxism, was profoundly influenced as a young man by the teachings of EpicurusTemplate:Sfn<ref>Karl Marx, Frederick Engels: Collected Works – Volume 1, p 30</ref> and his doctoral thesis was a Hegelian dialectical analysis of the differences between the natural philosophies of Democritus and Epicurus.Template:Sfn Marx viewed Democritus as a rationalist skeptic, whose epistemology was inherently contradictory, but saw Epicurus as a dogmatic empiricist, whose worldview is internally consistent and practically applicable.Template:Sfn The British poet Alfred Tennyson (1809–1892) praised "the sober majesties / of settled, sweet, Epicurean life" in his 1868 poem "Lucretius".Template:Sfn Epicurus's ethical teachings also had an indirect impact on the philosophy of Utilitarianism in England during the nineteenth century.Template:Sfn Soviet politician Joseph Stalin (1878–1953) lauded Epicurus by stating: "He was the greatest philosopher of all time. He was the one who recommended practicing virtue to derive the greatest joy from life".<ref>Template:Cite book</ref>
Friedrich Nietzsche once noted: "Even today many educated people think that the victory of Christianity over Greek philosophy is a proof of the superior truth of the former – although in this case it was only the coarser and more violent that conquered the more spiritual and delicate. So far as superior truth is concerned, it is enough to observe that the awakening sciences have allied themselves point by point with the philosophy of Epicurus, but point by point rejected Christianity."<ref>Friedrich Nietzsche: Human, All Too Human: A Book for Free Spirits, p. 44.</ref>
Academic interest in Epicurus and other Hellenistic philosophers increased over the course of the late twentieth and early twenty-first centuries, with an unprecedented number of monographs, articles, abstracts, and conference papers being published on the subject.Template:Sfn The texts from the library of Philodemus of Gadara in the Villa of the Papyri in Herculaneum, first discovered between 1750 and 1765, are being deciphered, translated, and published by scholars part of the Philodemus Translation Project, funded by the United States National Endowment for the Humanities, and part of the Centro per lo Studio dei Papiri Ercolanesi in Naples.Template:Sfn Epicurus's popular appeal among non-scholars is difficult to gauge,Template:Sfn but it seems to be relatively comparable to the appeal of more traditionally popular ancient Greek philosophical subjects such as Stoicism, Aristotle, and Plato.Template:Sfn
See also
[edit]Notes
[edit]References
[edit]Bibliography
[edit]- Template:Citation
- Template:Citation
- Template:Citation
- Template:Citation
- Template:Citation
- Template:Citation
- Template:Citation
- Template:Citation
- Template:Citation
- Template:Citation
- Template:Citation
- Template:Citation
- Template:Citation
- Template:Citation
- Template:Citation
- Template:Citation
- Template:Citation
Further reading
[edit]Texts
[edit]- Template:Cite book
- Template:Cite book
- Template:Cite book
- Template:Cite book
- Template:Cite book
- Template:Cite book
- Oates, Whitney J. (1940). The Stoic and Epicurean philosophers, The Complete Extant Writings of Epicurus, Epictetus, Lucretius and Marcus Aurelius. New York: Modern Library.
- Template:Cite book
Studies
[edit]- Bailey C. (1928). The Greek Atomists and Epicurus, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Template:Cite book
- Template:Cite book
- Template:Cite book
- Template:Cite book
- Template:Cite book
- Template:Cite book
- Template:Cite book
- Template:Cite journal
- Template:Cite book
- Template:Cite book
- Template:Cite book
- Template:Cite book
- William Wallace. Epicureanism. SPCK (1880)
External links
[edit]- Template:Wikisourcelang-inline
- Template:Wikisourcelang-inline
- Template:Cite SEP
- Template:Cite IEP
- Stoic And Epicurean by Robert Drew Hicks (1910) (Internet Archive)
- Epicurea, Hermann Usener - full text
- Template:Internet Archive author
- Template:Librivox author.
- Society of Friends of Epicurus
- Discussion Forum for Epicurus and Epicurean philosophy - EpicureanFriends.com
Template:Epicureanism Template:Greek schools of philosophy Template:Ancient Greece topics Template:Philosophy of science Template:Authority control
- Pages with broken file links
- 4th-century BC Greek philosophers
- 3rd-century BC Greek philosophers
- 341 BC births
- 270 BC deaths
- Ancient Greek epistemologists
- Ancient Greek ethicists
- Ancient Greek metaphysicians
- Ancient Greek philosophers of mind
- Ancient Greek physicists
- Ancient Samians
- Empiricists
- Epicurean philosophers
- Greek male writers
- Materialists
- Philosophers of death
- Hellenistic-era philosophers in Athens