Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Kaldor–Hicks efficiency
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Short description|State leading to a Pareto-efficient outcome, concerning the compensation principle}} {{Use dmy dates|date=September 2015}} {{more footnotes|date=April 2012}} A '''Kaldor–Hicks improvement''', named for [[Nicholas Kaldor]] and [[John Hicks]], is an economic re-allocation of resources among people that captures some of the intuitive appeal of a [[Pareto efficiency|Pareto improvement]], but has less stringent criteria and is hence applicable to more circumstances. A re-allocation is a Kaldor–Hicks improvement if those that are made better off could [[compensation principle|hypothetically compensate]] those that are made worse off and lead to a Pareto-improving outcome. The compensation does not actually have to occur (there is no presumption in favor of status-quo) and thus, a Kaldor–Hicks improvement can in fact leave some people worse off. A situation is said to be '''Kaldor–Hicks efficient''', or equivalently is said to satisfy the '''Kaldor–Hicks criterion''', if no potential Kaldor–Hicks improvement from that situation exists. If an outcome is the highest it could possibly be, it is called a Hicks-optimal outcome. A Hicks optimal outcome is always Pareto efficient. ==Explanation== A reallocation is said to be a [[Pareto improvement]] if at least one person is made better off and nobody is made worse off. However, in practice, it is almost impossible to take any social action, such as a change in economic policy, without making at least one person worse off. Even voluntary exchanges may not be Pareto improving if they make third parties worse off. Using the criterion for Kaldor–Hicks improvement, an outcome is an improvement if those that are made better off could in principle compensate those that are made worse off, so that a Pareto improving outcome ''could'' (though does not have to) be achieved. For example, a voluntary exchange that creates pollution would be a ''Kaldor–Hicks improvement'' if the buyers and sellers are still willing to carry out the transaction even if they have to fully compensate the victims of the pollution. Kaldor–Hicks does not require compensation actually be paid, merely that the possibility for compensation exists, and thus need not leave each at least as well off. Under Kaldor–Hicks efficiency, an improvement can in fact leave some people worse off. Pareto-improvements require making every party involved better off (or at least none worse off). While every Pareto improvement is a Kaldor–Hicks improvement, most Kaldor–Hicks improvements are not Pareto improvements. In other words, the set of Pareto improvements is a proper subset of Kaldor–Hicks improvements. This reflects the greater flexibility and applicability of the Kaldor–Hicks criterion relative to the Pareto criterion. ==Use in policy-making== The Kaldor–Hicks methods are typically used as tests of potential improvements rather than as efficiency goals themselves. They are used to determine whether an activity moves the economy toward Pareto efficiency. Any change usually makes some people better off and others worse off, so these tests consider what would happen if gainers were to compensate losers. The Kaldor criterion is that an activity moves the economy closer to Pareto optimality if the maximum amount the gainers are [[willingness to pay|prepared to pay]] to the losers to agree to the change is greater than the minimum amount losers are prepared to accept; the Hicks criterion is that an activity moves the economy toward Pareto optimality if the maximum amount the losers would pay the gainers to forgo the change is less than the minimum amount the gainers would accept to so agree. Thus, the Kaldor test supposes that losers could prevent the arrangement and asks whether gainers value their gain so much they would and could pay losers to accept the arrangement, whereas the Hicks test supposes that gainers are able to proceed with the change and asks whether losers consider their loss to be worth less than what it would cost them to pay gainers to agree ''not'' to proceed with the change. After several technical problems with each separate criterion were discovered, they were combined into the [[Scitovsky]] criterion, more commonly known as the "Kaldor–Hicks criterion", which does not share the same flaws. The Kaldor–Hicks criterion is widely applied in [[game theory]]'s non-zero sum games, such as [[DOTMLPF]], [[welfare economics]], and [[managerial economics]]. For example, it forms an underlying rationale for [[cost–benefit analysis]]. In cost–benefit analysis, a project (for example, a new airport) is evaluated by comparing the total costs, such as building costs and environmental costs, with the total benefits, such as airline profits and convenience for travelers. (However, as cost–benefit analysis may also assign different social welfare weights to different individuals, e.g. more to the poor, the compensation criterion is not always invoked by cost–benefit analysis.) The project would typically be given the go-ahead if the benefits exceed the costs. This is effectively an application of the Kaldor–Hicks criterion because it is equivalent to requiring that the benefits be enough that those that benefit could in theory compensate those that have lost out. The criterion is used because it is argued that it is justifiable for society as a whole to make some worse off if this means a greater gain for others. ==Criticisms== Perhaps the most common criticism of the Kaldor-Hicks criteria is that it is unclear why the ''capacity'' of the winners to compensate the losers should matter, or have moral or political significance as a decision criteria, if the compensation is not actually paid. At a more technical level, various versions of the Kaldor–Hicks criteria lack desirable formal properties. For instance, [[Tibor Scitovsky]] demonstrated that the Kaldor criterion alone is not [[Antisymmetric relation|antisymmetric]]: it's possible to have a situation where an outcome A is an improvement (according to the Kaldor criterion) over outcome B, but B is also an improvement over A. The combined Kaldor–Hicks criterion does not have this problem, but it can be [[Intransitivity|non-transitive]] (though A may be an improvement over B, and B over C, A is not thereby an improvement over C).<ref>{{cite journal |last=Scitovsky |first=T. |author-link=Tibor Scitovsky|year=1941 |title=A Note on Welfare Propositions in Economics |journal=Review of Economic Studies |volume=9 |issue=1 |pages=[https://www.hujingbei.net/upload/2007_11/07110714376633.pdf#page=2 77–88] |doi=10.2307/2967640 |jstor= 2967640|publisher=The Review of Economic Studies, Vol. 9, No. 1 }}</ref><ref>{{cite web |title=The Paretian System: Scitovsky Reversals and the Double Criteria |last=Fonseca |first=G. L. |url-status=dead |url=http://cepa.newschool.edu/het/essays/paretian/paretosocial.htm#scitovsky |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20060215000915/http://cepa.newschool.edu/het/essays/paretian/paretosocial.htm#scitovsky |archive-date=15 February 2006 |df=dmy-all }}</ref> ==See also== * [[Compensation principle]] * [[Pareto efficiency]] * [[Scitovsky paradox]] ==References== {{Reflist}} ==Further reading== *{{cite journal |last=Hicks |first=John |author-link=John Hicks |year=1939 |title=The Foundations of Welfare Economics |journal=[[The Economic Journal]] |pages=696–712 |doi=10.2307/2225023 |jstor= 2225023 |volume=49 |number=196 }} *{{cite journal |last=Kaldor |first=Nicholas |author-link=Nicholas Kaldor |year=1939 |title=Welfare Propositions in Economics and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility |journal=The Economic Journal |volume=49 |issue=195 |pages=549–552 |jstor= 2224835|doi=10.2307/2224835}} *{{cite book |title=Economic Analysis of Law |last=Posner |first=Richard A. |author-link=Richard Posner |edition=Seventh |year=2007 |publisher=[[Wolters Kluwer]] |location=Austin, TX |isbn=978-0-7355-6354-4}} == External links== {{Wikiquote-inline}} {{DEFAULTSORT:Kaldor-Hicks efficiency}} [[Category:Law and economics]] [[Category:Welfare economics]] [[Category:Pareto efficiency]] [[Category:1939 introductions]]
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Templates used on this page:
Template:Cite book
(
edit
)
Template:Cite journal
(
edit
)
Template:Cite web
(
edit
)
Template:More footnotes
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)
Template:Use dmy dates
(
edit
)
Template:Wikiquote-inline
(
edit
)
Search
Search
Editing
Kaldor–Hicks efficiency
Add topic