Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Concrete category
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{short description|Category equipped with a faithful functor to the category of sets}} In [[mathematics]], a '''concrete category''' is a [[category (category theory)|category]] that is equipped with a [[faithful functor]] to the [[category of sets]] (or sometimes to another category). This functor makes it possible to think of the objects of the category as sets with additional [[mathematical structure|structure]], and of its [[morphism]]s as structure-preserving functions. Many important categories have obvious interpretations as concrete categories, for example the [[category of topological spaces]] and the [[category of groups]], and trivially also the category of sets itself. On the other hand, the [[homotopy category of topological spaces]] is not '''concretizable''', i.e. it does not admit a faithful functor to the category of sets. A concrete category, when defined without reference to the notion of a category, consists of a [[class (set theory)|class]] of ''objects'', each equipped with an ''underlying set''; and for any two objects ''A'' and ''B'' a set of functions, called ''homomorphisms'', from the underlying set of ''A'' to the underlying set of ''B''. Furthermore, for every object ''A'', the identity function on the underlying set of ''A'' must be a homomorphism from ''A'' to ''A'', and the composition of a homomorphism from ''A'' to ''B'' followed by a homomorphism from ''B'' to ''C'' must be a homomorphism from ''A'' to ''C''.<ref>{{Citation | last1=Mac Lane | first1=Saunders | author1-link=Saunders Mac Lane | last2=Birkhoff | first2=Garrett | author2-link=Garrett Birkhoff | title=Algebra | publisher=AMS Chelsea | edition=3rd | isbn=978-0-8218-1646-2 | year=1999}}</ref> == Definition == A '''concrete category''' is a pair (''C'',''U'') such that *''C'' is a category, and *''U'' : ''C'' β '''Set''' (the category of sets and functions) is a [[faithful functor]]. The functor ''U'' is to be thought of as a [[forgetful functor]], which assigns to every object of ''C'' its "underlying set", and to every morphism in ''C'' its "underlying function". It is customary to call the morphisms in a concrete category ''homomorphisms'' (e.g., group homomorphisms, ring homomorphisms, etc.) Because of the faithfulness of the functor ''U'', the homomorphisms of a concrete category may be formally identified with their underlying functions (i.e., their images under ''U''); the homomorphisms then regain the usual interpretation as "structure-preserving" functions. A category ''C'' is '''concretizable''' if there exists a concrete category (''C'',''U''); i.e., if there exists a faithful functor ''U'': ''C'' β '''Set'''. All small categories are concretizable: define ''U'' so that its object part maps each object ''b'' of ''C'' to the set of all morphisms of ''C'' whose [[codomain]] is ''b'' (i.e. all morphisms of the form ''f'': ''a'' β ''b'' for any object ''a'' of ''C''), and its morphism part maps each morphism ''g'': ''b'' β ''c'' of ''C'' to the function ''U''(''g''): ''U''(''b'') β ''U''(''c'') which maps each member ''f'': ''a'' β ''b'' of ''U''(''b'') to the composition ''gf'': ''a'' β ''c'', a member of ''U''(''c''). (Item 6 under [[concrete category#Further examples|Further examples]] expresses the same ''U'' in less elementary language via presheaves.) The [[concrete category#Counter-examples|Counter-examples]] section exhibits two large categories that are not concretizable. == Remarks == Contrary to intuition, concreteness is not a [[property (philosophy)|property]] that a category may or may not satisfy, but rather a structure with which a category may or may not be equipped. In particular, a category ''C'' may admit several faithful functors into '''Set'''. Hence there may be several concrete categories (''C'', ''U'') all corresponding to the same category ''C''. In practice, however, the choice of faithful functor is often clear and in this case we simply speak of the "concrete category ''C''". For example, "the concrete category '''Set'''" means the pair ('''Set''', ''I'') where ''I'' denotes the [[identity functor]] '''Set''' β '''Set'''. The requirement that ''U'' be faithful means that it maps different morphisms between the same objects to different functions. However, ''U'' may map different objects to the same set and, if this occurs, it will also map different morphisms to the same function. For example, if ''S'' and ''T'' are two different topologies on the same set ''X'', then (''X'', ''S'') and (''X'', ''T'') are distinct objects in the category '''Top''' of topological spaces and continuous maps, but mapped to the same set ''X'' by the forgetful functor '''Top''' β '''Set'''. Moreover, the identity morphism (''X'', ''S'') β (''X'', ''S'') and the identity morphism (''X'', ''T'') β (''X'', ''T'') are considered distinct morphisms in '''Top''', but they have the same underlying function, namely the identity function on ''X''. Similarly, any set with four elements can be given two non-isomorphic group structures: one isomorphic to <math>\mathbb{Z}/2\mathbb{Z} \times \mathbb{Z}/2\mathbb{Z}</math>, and the other isomorphic to <math>\mathbb{Z}/4\mathbb{Z}</math>. == Further examples == # Any group ''G'' may be regarded as an "abstract" category with one arbitrary object, <math>\ast</math>, and one morphism for each element of the group. This would not be counted as concrete according to the intuitive notion described at the top of this article. But every faithful [[Group action (mathematics)|''G''-set]] (equivalently, every representation of ''G'' as a [[permutation group|group of permutations]]) determines a faithful functor ''G'' β '''Set'''. Since every group acts faithfully on itself, ''G'' can be made into a concrete category in at least one way. # Similarly, any [[poset]] ''P'' may be regarded as an abstract category with a unique arrow ''x'' β ''y'' whenever ''x'' β€ ''y''. This can be made concrete by defining a functor ''D'' : ''P'' β '''Set''' which maps each object ''x'' to <math>D(x)=\{a \in P : a \leq x\}</math> and each arrow ''x'' β ''y'' to the inclusion map <math>D(x) \hookrightarrow D(y)</math>. # The category '''[[Category of relations|Rel]]''' whose objects are [[Set (mathematics)|sets]] and whose morphisms are [[Relation (mathematics)|relations]] can be made concrete by taking ''U'' to map each set ''X'' to its power set <math>2^X</math> and each relation <math>R \subseteq X \times Y</math> to the function <math>\rho: 2^X \rightarrow 2^Y</math> defined by <math>\rho(A)=\{y \in Y \mid \exists \, x \in A : xRy\}</math>. Noting that power sets are [[complete lattice]]s under inclusion, those functions between them arising from some relation ''R'' in this way are exactly the [[Complete lattice#Morphisms of complete lattices|supremum-preserving maps]]. Hence '''Rel''' is equivalent to a full subcategory of the category '''Sup''' of [[complete lattices]] and their sup-preserving maps. Conversely, starting from this equivalence we can recover ''U'' as the composite '''Rel''' β '''Sup''' β '''Set''' of the forgetful functor for '''Sup''' with this embedding of '''Rel''' in '''Sup'''. # The category '''Set'''<sup>op</sup> can be embedded into '''Rel''' by representing each set as itself and each function ''f'': ''X'' β ''Y'' as the relation from ''Y'' to ''X'' formed as the set of pairs (''f''(''x''), ''x'') for all ''x'' β ''X''; hence '''Set'''<sup>op</sup> is concretizable. The forgetful functor which arises in this way is the [[Functor#Examples|contravariant powerset functor]] '''Set'''<sup>op</sup> β '''Set'''. # It follows from the previous example that the opposite of any concretizable category ''C'' is again concretizable, since if ''U'' is a faithful functor ''C'' β '''Set''' then ''C''<sup>op</sup> may be equipped with the composite ''C''<sup>op</sup> β '''Set'''<sup>op</sup> β '''Set'''. # If ''C'' is any small category, then there exists a faithful functor ''P'' : '''Set'''<sup>''C''<sup>op</sup></sup> β '''Set''' which maps a presheaf ''X'' to the coproduct <math>\coprod_{c \in \mathrm{ob}C} X(c)</math>. By composing this with the [[Yoneda embedding]] ''Y'':''C'' β '''Set'''<sup>''C''<sup>op</sup></sup> one obtains a faithful functor ''C'' β '''Set'''. # For technical reasons, the category '''Ban'''<sub>1</sub> of [[Banach spaces]] and [[contraction (operator theory)|linear contractions]] is often equipped not with the "obvious" forgetful functor but the functor ''U''<sub>1</sub> : '''Ban'''<sub>1</sub> β '''Set''' which maps a Banach space to its (closed) [[unit ball]]. #The category '''Cat''' whose objects are small categories and whose morphisms are functors can be made concrete by sending each category '''C''' to the set containing its objects and morphisms. Functors can be simply viewed as functions acting on the objects and morphisms. == Counter-examples == The category '''[[homotopy category of topological spaces|hTop]]''', where the objects are [[topological space]]s and the morphisms are [[homotopy|homotopy classes]] of continuous functions, is an example of a category that is not concretizable. While the objects are sets (with additional structure), the morphisms are not actual functions between them, but rather classes of functions. The fact that there does not exist ''any'' faithful functor from '''hTop''' to '''Set''' was first proven by [[Peter Freyd]]. In the same article, Freyd cites an earlier result that the category of "small categories and [[natural equivalence]]-classes of functors" also fails to be concretizable. == Implicit structure of concrete categories == Given a concrete category (''C'', ''U'') and a [[cardinal number]] ''N'', let ''U<sup>N</sup>'' be the functor ''C'' β '''Set''' determined by ''U<sup>N</sup>(c) = (U(c))<sup>N</sup>''. Then a [[subfunctor]] of ''U<sup>N</sup>'' is called an ''N-ary predicate'' and a [[natural transformation]] ''U<sup>N</sup>'' β ''U'' an ''N-ary operation''. The class of all ''N''-ary predicates and ''N''-ary operations of a concrete category (''C'',''U''), with ''N'' ranging over the class of all cardinal numbers, forms a [[proper class|large]] [[signature (logic)|signature]]. The category of models for this signature then contains a full subcategory which is [[equivalence of categories|equivalent]] to ''C''. == Relative concreteness == In some parts of category theory, most notably [[topos theory]], it is common to replace the category '''Set''' with a different category ''X'', often called a ''base category''. For this reason, it makes sense to call a pair (''C'', ''U'') where ''C'' is a category and ''U'' a faithful functor ''C'' β ''X'' a '''concrete category over''' ''X''. For example, it may be useful to think of the models of a theory [[Structure (mathematical logic)#Many-sorted structures|with ''N'' sorts]] as forming a concrete category over '''Set'''<sup>''N''</sup>. In this context, a concrete category over '''Set''' is sometimes called a ''construct''. == Notes == <references /> == References == {{refbegin}} * AdΓ‘mek, JiΕΓ, Herrlich, Horst, & Strecker, George E.; (1990). [http://katmat.math.uni-bremen.de/acc/acc.pdf ''Abstract and Concrete Categories''] (4.2MB PDF). Originally publ. John Wiley & Sons. {{ISBN|0-471-60922-6}}. (now free on-line edition). * Freyd, Peter; (1970). [http://www.tac.mta.ca/tac/reprints/articles/6/tr6abs.html ''Homotopy is not concrete'']. Originally published in: The Steenrod Algebra and its Applications, Springer Lecture Notes in Mathematics Vol. 168. Republished in a free on-line journal: Reprints in Theory and Applications of Categories, No. 6 (2004), with the permission of Springer-Verlag. * RosickΓ½, JiΕΓ; (1981). ''Concrete categories and infinitary languages''. [http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/journal/00224049 ''Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra''], Volume 22, Issue 3. {{refend}} [[Category:Category theory]]
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Templates used on this page:
Template:Citation
(
edit
)
Template:ISBN
(
edit
)
Template:Refbegin
(
edit
)
Template:Refend
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)
Search
Search
Editing
Concrete category
Add topic