Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Axiom of choice
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Short description|Axiom of set theory}} {{About|the mathematical concept|the band|Axiom of Choice (band)}} {{Redirect-distinguish|ZF¬C|ZFC (disambiguation)}} {{Use dmy dates|date=October 2021}} [[File:Axiome du choix.png|thumb|250px|Illustration of the axiom of choice, with each set ''S''<sub>''i''</sub> represented as a jar and its elements represented as marbles. Each element ''x''<sub>''i''</sub> is represented as a marble on the right. Colors are used to suggest a functional association of marbles after adopting the choice axiom. The existence of such a choice function is in general independent of ZF for collections of infinite cardinality, even if all ''S''<sub>''i''</sub> are finite.]] [[File:Axiom of choice.svg|thumb|250px|(S<sub>''i''</sub>) is an infinite [[indexed family]] of sets indexed over the [[real number]]s '''R'''; that is, there is a set S<sub>''i''</sub> for each real number ''i'', with a small sample shown above. Each set contains at least one, and possibly infinitely many, elements. The axiom of choice allows us to select a single element from each set, forming a corresponding family of elements (''x''<sub>''i''</sub>) also indexed over the real numbers, with ''x''<sub>''i''</sub> drawn from S<sub>''i''</sub>. In general, the collections may be indexed over any set <span style="font-family:serif;">''I''</span>, (called index set whose elements are used as indices for elements in a set) not just '''R'''.]] In [[mathematics]], the '''axiom of choice''', abbreviated '''AC''' or '''AoC''', is an [[axiom]] of [[set theory]]. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any [[Family of sets|collection]] of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from each set, even if the collection is [[Infinite set|infinite]]. Formally, it states that for every [[indexed family]] <math>(S_i)_{i \in I}</math> of [[nonempty]] sets, there exists an indexed set <math>(x_i)_{i \in I}</math> such that <math>x_i \in S_i</math> for every <math>i \in I</math>. The axiom of choice was formulated in 1904 by [[Ernst Zermelo]] in order to formalize his proof of the [[well-ordering theorem]].{{sfn|Zermelo|1904}} The axiom of choice is equivalent to the statement that every [[partition of a set|partition]] has a [[transversal (combinatorics)|transversal]].<ref>{{cite web|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/axiom-choice/|title=The Axiom of Choice|website=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|first=Bell|last=John|date=December 10, 2021|access-date=December 2, 2024|quote=Let us call Zermelo’s 1908 formulation the combinatorial axiom of choice: CAC: Any collection of mutually disjoint nonempty sets has a transversal.}}</ref> In many cases, a set created by choosing elements can be made without invoking the axiom of choice, particularly if the number of sets from which to choose the elements is finite, or if a canonical rule on how to choose the elements is available — some distinguishing property that happens to hold for exactly one element in each set. An illustrative example is sets picked from the natural numbers. From such sets, one may always select the smallest number, e.g. given the sets <nowiki>{{4, 5, 6}, {10, 12}, {1, 400, 617, 8000}}</nowiki>, the set containing each smallest element is {4, 10, 1}. In this case, "select the smallest number" is a [[choice function]]. Even if infinitely many sets are collected from the natural numbers, it will always be possible to choose the smallest element from each set to produce a set. That is, the choice function provides the set of chosen elements. But no definite choice function is known for the collection of all non-empty subsets of the real numbers. In that case, the axiom of choice must be invoked. [[Bertrand Russell]] coined an analogy: for any (even infinite) collection of pairs of shoes, one can pick out the left shoe from each pair to obtain an appropriate collection (i.e. set) of shoes; this makes it possible to define a choice function directly. For an ''infinite'' collection of pairs of socks (assumed to have no distinguishing features such as being a left sock rather than a right sock), there is no obvious way to make a function that forms a set out of selecting one sock from each pair without invoking the axiom of choice.{{sfn|Jech|1977|p=351}} Although originally controversial, the axiom of choice is now used without reservation by most mathematicians,<ref>{{harvnb|Jech|1977|p=348 ff}}; {{harvnb|Mac Lane|1986|pages=366-367}}; {{harvnb|Martin-Löf|2008|p=210}}. According to {{harvnb|Mendelson|1964|p=201}}: "The status of the Axiom of Choice has become less controversial in recent years. To most mathematicians it seems quite plausible and it has so many important applications in practically all branches of mathematics that not to accept it would seem to be a wilful hobbling of the practicing mathematician."</ref> and is included in the standard form of [[axiomatic set theory]], [[Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory]] with the axiom of choice (ZFC). One motivation for this is that a number of generally accepted mathematical results, such as [[Tychonoff's theorem]], require the axiom of choice for their proofs. Contemporary set theorists also study axioms that are not compatible with the axiom of choice, such as the [[axiom of determinacy]]. The axiom of choice is avoided in some varieties of [[Constructivism (mathematics)|constructive mathematics]], although there are varieties of constructive mathematics in which the axiom of choice is embraced. ==Statement== A [[choice function]] (also called selector or selection) is a function <math>f</math>, defined on a collection <math>X</math> of nonempty sets, such that for every set <math>A</math> in <math>X</math>, <math>f(A)</math> is an element of <math>A</math>. With this concept, the axiom can be stated: {{math theorem|For any set <math>X</math> of nonempty sets, there exists a choice function ''f'' that is defined on <math>X</math> and maps each set of <math>X</math> to an element of that set. | name = Axiom }} Formally, this may be expressed as follows: :<math>\forall X \left[ \varnothing \notin X \implies \exists f \colon X \rightarrow \bigcup_{A\in X} A \quad \forall A \in X \, ( f(A) \in A ) \right] \,.</math> Thus, the [[negation]] of the axiom may be expressed as the existence of a collection of nonempty sets which has no choice function. Formally, this may be derived making use of the logical equivalence of :<math> \neg \forall X \left[ P(X)\to Q(X) \right] \quad \iff \quad \exists X \left[ P(X)\land \neg Q(X) \right]. </math> Each choice function on a collection <math>X</math> of nonempty sets is an element of the [[Cartesian product#Infinite products|Cartesian product]] of the sets in <math>X</math>. This is not the most general situation of a Cartesian product of a [[indexed family|family]] of sets, where a given set can occur more than once as a factor; however, one can focus on elements of such a product that select the same element every time a given set appears as factor, and such elements correspond to an element of the Cartesian product of all ''distinct'' sets in the family. The axiom of choice asserts the existence of such elements; it is therefore equivalent to the statement: :''There exists a non-empty [[Cartesian product]] of a collection of non-empty sets'' ===Nomenclature=== In this article and other discussions of the Axiom of Choice the following abbreviations are common: *AC – the Axiom of Choice. More rarely, AoC is used.{{sfn|Rosenberg|2021}} *ZF – [[Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory]] omitting the Axiom of Choice. *ZFC – Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, extended to include the Axiom of Choice. ===Variants=== There are many other equivalent statements of the axiom of choice. These are equivalent in the sense that, in the presence of other basic axioms of set theory, they imply the axiom of choice and are implied by it. One variation avoids the use of choice functions by, in effect, replacing each choice function with its range: :Given any set <math>X</math>, if the empty set is not an element of <math>X</math> and the elements of <math>X</math> are [[pairwise disjoint]], then there exists a set <math>C</math> such that its intersection with any of the elements of <math>X</math> contains exactly one element.<ref>{{harvnb|Herrlich|2006|p=9}}. According to {{harvnb|Suppes|1972|p=243}}, this was the formulation of the axiom of choice which was originally given by {{harvnb|Zermelo|1904}}. See also {{harvnb|Halmos|1960|p=60}} for this formulation.</ref> This can be formalized in first-order logic as: <math> \begin{align} \forall x (& \\ &\exists e (e \in x \and \lnot\exists y (y \in e)) \or \\ &\exists a \, \exists b \, \exists c \, (a \in x \and b \in x \and c \in a \and c \in b \and \lnot(a = b)) \or \\ &\exists c \, \forall e \, (e \in x \implies \exists a \, (a \in e \and a \in c \and \forall b \, ((b \in e \and b \in c) \implies a = b)))) \end{align} </math> Note that <math>P \or Q \or R</math> is logically equivalent to <math>(\lnot P \and \lnot Q) \implies R</math>.<br> In English, this first-order sentence reads: :Given any set <math>X</math>, :<math>X</math> contains the empty set as an element or :the elements of <math>X</math> are not pairwise disjoint or :there exists a set <math>X</math> such that its intersection with any of the elements of <math>X</math> contains exactly one element. This guarantees for any [[partition of a set]] <math>X</math> the existence of a subset <math>C</math> of <math>X</math> containing exactly one element from each part of the partition. Another equivalent axiom only considers collections <math>X</math> that are essentially powersets of other sets: :For any set <math>A</math>, the [[power set]] of <math>A</math> (with the empty set removed) has a choice function. Authors who use this formulation often speak of the ''choice function on <math>A</math>'', but this is a slightly different notion of choice function. Its domain is the power set of <math>A</math> (with the empty set removed), and so makes sense for any set <math>A</math>, whereas with the definition used elsewhere in this article, the domain of a choice function on a ''collection of sets'' is that collection, and so only makes sense for sets of sets. With this alternate notion of choice function, the axiom of choice can be compactly stated as :Every set has a choice function.{{sfn|Suppes|1972|p=240}} which is equivalent to :For any set <math>A</math> there is a function <math>f:\mathcal P(A)\setminus\{ \emptyset \} \to A </math> such that for any non-empty subset <math>B</math> of <math>A</math>, <math>f(B)</math> lies in <math>B</math>. The negation of the axiom can thus be expressed as: :There is a set <math>A</math> such that for all functions <math>f</math> (on the set of non-empty subsets of <math>A</math>), there is a subset <math>B</math> such that <math>f(B)</math> does not lie in <math>B</math>. ===Restriction to finite sets=== The usual statement of the axiom of choice does not specify whether the collection of nonempty sets is finite or infinite, and thus implies that every [[finite set|finite collection]] of nonempty sets has a choice function. However, that particular case is a theorem of the Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice (ZF); it is easily proved by the [[mathematical induction|principle of finite induction]].{{sfn|Tourlakis|2003|pp=209–210, 215–216}} In the even simpler case of a collection of ''one'' set, a choice function just corresponds to an element, so this instance of the axiom of choice says that every nonempty set has an element; this holds trivially. The axiom of choice can be seen as asserting the generalization of this property, already evident for finite collections, to arbitrary collections. ==Usage== Until the late 19th century, the axiom of choice was often used implicitly, although it had not yet been formally stated. For example, after having established that the set ''X'' contains only non-empty sets, a mathematician might have said "let ''F''(''s'') be one of the members of ''s'' for all ''s'' in ''X''" to define a function ''F''. In general, it is impossible to prove that ''F'' exists without the axiom of choice, but this seems to have gone unnoticed until [[Zermelo]]. <!--Not every situation requires the full axiom of choice. For a finite collection of sets ''X'', the axiom of choice follows from the other axioms of set theory. In that case, it is equivalent to saying that if we have several (a finite number of) boxes, each containing at least one item, then we can choose exactly one item from each box. Clearly, we can do this with the principle of finite induction: We start at the first box, choose an item; go to the second box, choose an item; and so on. The number of boxes is finite, so induction guarantees that our choice procedure is well-defined and eventually terminates. The result is an explicit choice function: a function that takes the first box to the first element we chose, the second box to the second element we chose, and so on. This shows that the axiom of choice restricted to finite sets (i.e., the statement "for every natural number ''k'', every family of ''k'' nonempty sets has a choice function") is a direct consequence of the axiom of finite induction and does not need anything beyond ZF. However, this argument will not work if the collection of sets ''X'' is infinite. For example, to show that every infinite sequence of nonempty sets has a choice function, as is asserted by the [[axiom of countable choice]], one needs to go beyond finite induction to countably transfinite induction. If the above method is applied to an infinite sequence (''X''<sub>''i''</sub> : ''i''∈ω) of nonempty sets, a function is obtained at each finite stage, but there is no stage at which a choice function for the entire family is constructed, and no "limiting" choice function can be constructed, in general (within ZF). Countable transfinite induction (a.k.a. the [[axiom of dependent choice]]) essentially guarantees the existence of such a "limiting" choice function, and thus implies the axiom of countable choice. It is however weaker than the full axiom of choice.--> <!--This whole section needs rewriting; it says something kind of true, but equates choice with induction, which is wrong. Choice is induction plus choosing. --> ==Examples== The nature of the individual nonempty sets in the collection may make it possible to avoid the axiom of choice even for certain infinite collections. For example, suppose that each member of the collection ''X'' is a nonempty subset of the natural numbers. Every such subset has a smallest element, so to specify our choice function we can simply say that it maps each set to the least element of that set. This gives us a definite choice of an element from each set, and makes it unnecessary to add the axiom of choice to our axioms of set theory. The difficulty appears when there is no natural choice of elements from each set. If we cannot make explicit choices, how do we know that our selection forms a legitimate set (as defined by the other ZF axioms of set theory)? For example, suppose that ''X'' is the set of all non-empty subsets of the [[real number]]s. First we might try to proceed as if ''X'' were finite. If we try to choose an element from each set, then, because ''X'' is infinite, our choice procedure will never come to an end, and consequently we shall never be able to produce a choice function for all of ''X''. Next we might try specifying the least element from each set. But some subsets of the real numbers do not have least elements. For example, the open [[Interval (mathematics)|interval]] (0,1) does not have a least element: if ''x'' is in (0,1), then so is ''x''/2, and ''x''/2 is always strictly smaller than ''x''. So this attempt also fails. Additionally, consider for instance the unit circle ''S'', and the action on ''S'' by a group ''G'' consisting of all rational rotations, that is, rotations by angles which are rational multiples of ''π''. Here ''G'' is countable while ''S'' is uncountable. Hence ''S'' breaks up into uncountably many orbits under ''G''. Using the axiom of choice, we could pick a single point from each orbit, obtaining an uncountable subset ''X'' of ''S'' with the property that all of its translates by ''G'' are disjoint from ''X''. The set of those translates partitions the circle into a countable collection of pairwise disjoint sets, which are all pairwise congruent. Since ''X'' is not measurable for any rotation-invariant countably additive finite measure on ''S'', finding an algorithm to form a set from selecting a point in each orbit requires that one add the axiom of choice to our axioms of set theory. See [[non-measurable set#Example|non-measurable set]] for more details. In classical arithmetic, the natural numbers are [[well-order]]ed: for every nonempty subset of the natural numbers, there is a unique least element under the natural ordering. In this way, one may specify a set from any given subset. One might say, "Even though the usual ordering of the real numbers does not work, it may be possible to find a different ordering of the real numbers which is a well-ordering. Then our choice function can choose the least element of every set under our unusual ordering." The problem then becomes that of constructing a well-ordering, which turns out to require the axiom of choice for its existence; every set can be well-ordered if and only if the axiom of choice holds. ==Criticism and acceptance== A proof requiring the axiom of choice may establish the existence of an object without explicitly [[definable set|defining]] the object in the language of set theory. For example, while the axiom of choice implies that there is a [[well-ordering]] of the real numbers, there are models of set theory with the axiom of choice in which no individual well-ordering of the reals is definable. Similarly, although a subset of the real numbers that is not [[Lebesgue measure|Lebesgue measurable]] can be proved to exist using the axiom of choice, it is [[consistent]] that no such set is definable.{{sfn|Fraenkel|Bar-Hillel|Lévy|1973|pp=69–70}} The axiom of choice asserts the existence of these intangibles (objects that are proved to exist, but which cannot be explicitly constructed), which may conflict with some philosophical principles.{{sfn|Rosenbloom|2005|page=147}} Because there is no [[Canonical form|canonical]] well-ordering of all sets, a construction that relies on a well-ordering may not produce a canonical result, even if a canonical result is desired (as is often the case in [[category theory]]). This has been used as an argument against the use of the axiom of choice. Another argument against the axiom of choice is that it implies the existence of objects that may seem counterintuitive.<ref>{{harvnb|Dawson|2006}}: "The axiom of choice, though it had been employed unconsciously in many arguments in analysis, became controversial once made explicit, not only because of its non-constructive character, but because it implied such extremely unintuitive consequences as the Banach–Tarski paradox."</ref> One example is the [[Banach–Tarski paradox]], which says that it is possible to decompose the 3-dimensional solid unit ball into finitely many pieces and, using only rotations and translations, reassemble the pieces into two solid balls each with the same volume as the original. The pieces in this decomposition, constructed using the axiom of choice, are [[non-measurable set]]s. Despite these seemingly paradoxical results, most mathematicians accept the axiom of choice as a valid principle for proving new results in mathematics. But the debate is interesting enough that it is considered notable when a theorem in ZFC (ZF plus AC) is [[logical equivalence|logically equivalent]] (with just the ZF axioms) to the axiom of choice, and mathematicians look for results that require the axiom of choice to be false, though this type of deduction is less common than the type that requires the axiom of choice to be true. Theorems of ZF hold true in any [[model theory|model]] of that theory, regardless of the truth or falsity of the axiom of choice in that particular model. The implications of choice below, including weaker versions of the axiom itself, are listed because they are not theorems of ZF. The Banach–Tarski paradox, for example, is neither provable nor disprovable from ZF alone: it is impossible to construct the required decomposition of the unit ball in ZF, but also impossible to prove there is no such decomposition. Such statements can be rephrased as conditional statements—for example, "If AC holds, then the decomposition in the Banach–Tarski paradox exists." Such conditional statements are provable in ZF when the original statements are provable from ZF and the axiom of choice. ==In constructive mathematics== As discussed above, in the classical theory of ZFC, the axiom of choice enables [[nonconstructive proof]]s in which the existence of a type of object is proved without an explicit instance being constructed. In fact, in set theory and [[topos theory]], [[Diaconescu's theorem]] shows that the axiom of choice implies the [[law of excluded middle]]. The principle is thus not available in [[constructive set theory]], where non-classical logic is employed. The situation is different when the principle is formulated in [[Martin-Löf type theory]]. There and higher-order [[Heyting arithmetic]], the appropriate statement of the axiom of choice is (depending on approach) included as an axiom or provable as a theorem.<ref>[[Per Martin-Löf]], ''[https://www.cs.cmu.edu/afs/cs/Web/People/crary/819-f09/Martin-Lof80.pdf Intuitionistic type theory]'', 1980. [[Anne Sjerp Troelstra]], ''Metamathematical investigation of intuitionistic arithmetic and analysis'', Springer, 1973.</ref> A cause for this difference is that the axiom of choice in type theory does not have the [[extensionality]] properties that the axiom of choice in constructive set theory does.<ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Martin-Löf | first1 = Per | author-link = Per Martin-Löf | year = 2006 | title = 100 Years of Zermelo's Axiom of Choice: What was the Problem with It? | journal = The Computer Journal | volume = 49 | issue = 3| pages = 345–350 | doi = 10.1093/comjnl/bxh162 | bibcode = 1980CompJ..23..262L }}</ref> The type theoretical context is discussed further below. Different choice principles have been thoroughly studied in the constructive contexts and the principles' status varies between different school and varieties of the constructive mathematics. Some results in constructive set theory use the [[axiom of countable choice]] or the [[axiom of dependent choice]], which do not imply the law of the excluded middle. [[Errett Bishop]], who is notable for developing a framework for constructive analysis, argued that an axiom of choice was constructively acceptable, saying {{blockquote|A choice function exists in constructive mathematics, because a choice is implied by the very meaning of existence.<ref>[[Errett Bishop]] and [[Douglas S. Bridges]], ''Constructive analysis'', Springer-Verlag, 1985.</ref>}} Although the axiom of countable choice in particular is commonly used in constructive mathematics, its use has also been questioned.<ref>Fred Richman, "Constructive mathematics without choice", in: Reuniting the Antipodes—Constructive and Nonstandard Views of the Continuum (P. Schuster et al., eds), Synthèse Library 306, 199–205, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Amsterdam, 2001.</ref> ==Independence== {{See also|List of statements independent of ZFC}} It has been known since as early as 1922 that the axiom of choice may fail in a variant of ZF with [[urelement]]s, through the technique of [[permutation model]]s introduced by [[Abraham Fraenkel]]{{sfn|Fraenkel|1922}} and developed further by [[Andrzej Mostowski]].{{sfn|Mostowski|1938}} The basic technique can be illustrated as follows: Let ''x''<sub>''n''</sub> and ''y''<sub>''n''</sub> be distinct urelements for {{nowrap|1=''n''=1, 2, 3...}}, and build a model where each set is symmetric under the interchange ''x''<sub>''n''</sub> ↔ ''y''<sub>''n''</sub> for all but a finite number of ''n''. Then the set {{nowrap|1=''X'' = {<!-- -->{''x''<sub>1</sub>, ''y''<sub>1</sub>}, {''x''<sub>2</sub>, ''y''<sub>2</sub>}, {''x''<sub>3</sub>, ''y''<sub>3</sub>}, ...} }} can be in the model but sets such as {{nowrap|{''x''<sub>1</sub>, ''x''<sub>2</sub>, ''x''<sub>3</sub>, ...} }} cannot, and thus ''X'' cannot have a choice function. In 1938,<ref>{{Cite journal|title=The Consistency of the Axiom of Choice and of the Generalized Continuum-Hypothesis|journal = Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America|volume = 24|issue = 12|pages = 556–557|last=Gödel|first=Kurt|date=9 November 1938|pmc = 1077160|pmid = 16577857|bibcode = 1938PNAS...24..556G|doi = 10.1073/pnas.24.12.556|doi-access = free}}</ref> [[Kurt Gödel]] showed that the ''negation'' of the axiom of choice is not a theorem of ZF by constructing an [[inner model]] (the [[constructible universe]]) that satisfies ZFC, thus showing that ZFC is consistent if ZF itself is consistent. In 1963, [[Paul Cohen (mathematician)|Paul Cohen]] employed the technique of [[forcing (mathematics)|forcing]], developed for this purpose, to show that, assuming ZF is consistent, the axiom of choice itself is not a theorem of ZF. He did this by constructing a much more complex model that satisfies ZF¬C (ZF with the negation of AC added as axiom) and thus showing that ZF¬C is consistent. Cohen's model is a [[symmetric model]], which is similar to permutation models, but uses "generic" subsets of the natural numbers (justified by forcing) in place of urelements.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://stacks.stanford.edu/file/druid:pd104gy5838/SCM0405.pdf |archive-url=https://ghostarchive.org/archive/20221009/https://stacks.stanford.edu/file/druid:pd104gy5838/SCM0405.pdf |archive-date=2022-10-09 |url-status=live|title=The Independence of the Axiom of Choice|last=Cohen|first=Paul|date=2019|website=Stanford University Libraries|access-date=2019-03-22}}</ref> Together these results establish that the axiom of choice is [[Independence (mathematical logic)|logically independent]] of ZF. The assumption that ZF is consistent is harmless because adding another axiom to an already inconsistent system cannot make the situation worse. Because of independence, the decision whether to use the axiom of choice (or its negation) in a proof cannot be made by appeal to other axioms of set theory. It must be made on other grounds. One argument in favor of using the axiom of choice is that it is convenient because it allows one to prove some simplifying propositions that otherwise could not be proved. Many theorems provable using choice are of an elegant general character: the cardinalities of any two sets are comparable, every nontrivial [[Ring (mathematics)|ring]] with unity has a [[maximal ideal]], every [[vector space]] has a [[Basis (linear algebra)|basis]], every [[connected graph]] has a [[spanning tree]], and every [[Product topology|product]] of [[compact space]]s is compact, among many others. Frequently, the axiom of choice allows generalizing a theorem to "larger" objects. For example, it is provable without the axiom of choice that every vector space of finite dimension has a basis, but the generalization to all vector spaces requires the axiom of choice. Likewise, a finite product of compact spaces can be proven to be compact without the axiom of choice, but the generalization to infinite products ([[Tychonoff's theorem]]) requires the axiom of choice. The proof of the independence result also shows that a wide class of mathematical statements, including all statements that can be phrased in the language of [[Peano arithmetic]], are provable in ZF if and only if they are provable in ZFC.<ref>This is because arithmetical statements are [[absoluteness (mathematical logic)|absolute]] to the [[constructible universe]] ''L''. [[Shoenfield's absoluteness theorem]] gives a more general result.</ref> Statements in this class include the statement that [[P = NP]], the [[Riemann hypothesis]], and many other unsolved mathematical problems. When attempting to solve problems in this class, it makes no difference whether ZF or ZFC is employed if the only question is the existence of a proof. It is possible, however, that there is a shorter proof of a theorem from ZFC than from ZF. The axiom of choice is not the only significant statement that is independent of ZF. For example, the [[Continuum hypothesis#The generalized continuum hypothesis|generalized continuum hypothesis]] (GCH) is not only independent of ZF, but also independent of ZFC. However, ZF plus GCH implies AC, making GCH a strictly stronger claim than AC, even though they are both independent of ZF. ==Stronger axioms== The [[axiom of constructibility]] and the [[Continuum hypothesis#The generalized continuum hypothesis|generalized continuum hypothesis]] each imply the axiom of choice and so are strictly stronger than it. In class theories such as [[Von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory]] and [[Morse–Kelley set theory]], there is an axiom called the [[axiom of global choice]] that is stronger than the axiom of choice for sets because it also applies to proper classes. The axiom of global choice follows from the [[axiom of limitation of size]]. Tarski's axiom, which is used in [[Tarski–Grothendieck set theory]] and states (in the vernacular) that every set belongs to {{em|some}} [[Grothendieck universe]], is stronger than the axiom of choice. ==Equivalents== There are important statements that, assuming the axioms of [[Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory|ZF]] but neither AC nor ¬AC, are equivalent to the axiom of choice.<ref>See {{harvnb|Moore|2013|pages=330–334}}, for a structured list of 74 equivalents. See {{harvnb|Howard|Rubin|1998|pp=11–16}}, for 86 equivalents with source references.</ref> The most important among them are [[Zorn's lemma]] and the [[well-ordering theorem]]. In fact, Zermelo initially introduced the axiom of choice in order to formalize his proof of the well-ordering theorem. *[[Set theory]] **[[Tarski's theorem about choice]]: For every infinite set ''A'', there is a [[bijective map]] between the sets ''A'' and ''A''×''A''. **[[Trichotomy (mathematics)|Trichotomy]]: If two sets are given, then either they have the same cardinality, or one has a smaller cardinality than the other. **Given two non-empty sets, one has a surjection to the other. **Every [[surjective function]] has a [[Inverse function#Left and right inverses|right inverse]]. **The [[Cartesian product#Infinite Cartesian products|Cartesian product]] of any family of nonempty sets is nonempty. In other words, every family of nonempty sets has a choice function (''i.e.'' a function which maps each of the nonempty sets to one of its elements). **[[König's theorem (set theory)|König's theorem]]: Colloquially, the sum of a sequence of cardinals is strictly less than the product of a sequence of larger cardinals. (The reason for the term "colloquially" is that the sum or product of a "sequence" of cardinals cannot itself be defined without some aspect of the axiom of choice.) **[[Well-ordering theorem]]: Every set can be well-ordered. Consequently, every [[cardinal number|cardinal]] has an [[initial ordinal]]. **[[Zorn's lemma]]: Every non-empty partially ordered set in which every chain (''i.e.'', totally ordered subset) has an upper bound contains at least one maximal element. **[[Hausdorff maximal principle]]: Every partially ordered set has a maximal chain. Equivalently, in any partially ordered set, every chain can be extended to a maximal chain. **[[Tukey's lemma]]: Every non-empty collection of [[finite character]] has a maximal element with respect to inclusion. **[[Antichain]] principle: Every partially ordered set has a maximal [[antichain]]. Equivalently, in any partially ordered set, every antichain can be extended to a maximal antichain. **The powerset of any ordinal can be well-ordered. *[[Abstract algebra]] **Every [[vector space]] has a [[basis (linear algebra)|basis]] (''i.e.'', a linearly independent spanning subset). In other words, vector spaces are equivalent to free modules.<ref>{{cite conference | last = Blass | first = Andreas | contribution = Existence of bases implies the axiom of choice | doi = 10.1090/conm/031/763890 | mr = 763890 | pages = 31–33 | publisher = American Mathematical Society | location = Providence, RI | series = Contemporary Mathematics | title = Axiomatic set theory (Boulder, Colo., 1983) | volume = 31 | year = 1984| isbn = 978-0-8218-5026-8 }}</ref> **[[Krull's theorem]]: Every unital [[ring (mathematics)|ring]] (other than the trivial ring) contains a [[maximal ideal]]. Equivalently, in any nontrivial unital ring, every ideal can be extended to a maximal ideal. **For every non-empty set ''S'' there is a [[binary operation]] defined on ''S'' that gives it a [[group (mathematics)|group structure]].<ref>{{harvnb|Hajnal|Kertész|1972}}, see also {{harvnb|Rubin|Rubin|1985|p=111}}.</ref> (A [[cancellation property|cancellative]] binary operation is enough, see [[group structure and the axiom of choice]].) **Every [[free abelian group]] is [[projective module|projective]].{{sfn|Blass|1979}} **Baer's criterion: Every [[divisible group|divisible abelian group]] is [[injective module|injective]].{{sfn|Blass|1979}} **Every set is a [[projective object]] in the [[Category (mathematics)|category]] '''[[Category of sets|Set]]''' of sets.<ref>{{Cite book|title=Category theory|url=https://archive.org/details/categorytheoryse00awod|url-access=limited|last=Awodey|first=Steve|date=2010|publisher=Oxford University Press|isbn=978-0199237180|edition=2nd|location=Oxford|pages=[https://archive.org/details/categorytheoryse00awod/page/n36 20]–24|oclc=740446073}}</ref><ref>{{nlab|id=projective+object|title=projective object}}</ref> *[[Functional analysis]] **The closed unit ball of the dual of a [[normed vector space]] over the reals has an [[extreme point]]. *[[Point-set topology]] **The [[product topology|Cartesian product]] of any family of [[connected space|connected]] [[topological space]]s is connected. **[[Tychonoff's theorem]]: The Cartesian product of any family of [[Compact space|compact]] topological spaces is compact. **In the product topology, the [[closure (topology)|closure]] of a product of subsets is equal to the product of the closures. *[[Mathematical logic]] **If ''S'' is a set of sentences of [[first-order logic]] and ''B'' is a consistent subset of ''S'', then ''B'' is included in a set that is maximal among consistent subsets of ''S''. The special case where ''S'' is the set of '''all''' first-order sentences in a given [[signature (logic)|signature]] is weaker, equivalent to the [[Boolean prime ideal theorem]]; see the section "Weaker forms" below. **[[Lowenheim-Skolem theorem]]: If first-order theory has infinite model, then it has infinite model of every possible cardinality greater than cardinality of language of this theory. *[[Graph theory]] **Every [[connected graph]] has a [[spanning tree]]. Equivalently, every nonempty graph has a spanning forest.<ref>{{citation|title=Trees|first=Jean-Pierre|last=Serre|author-link=Jean-Pierre Serre|page=23|publisher=Springer|series=Springer Monographs in Mathematics|year=2003}}; {{citation | last = Soukup | first = Lajos | contribution = Infinite combinatorics: from finite to infinite | doi = 10.1007/978-3-540-77200-2_10 | location = Berlin | mr = 2432534 | pages = 189–213 | publisher = Springer | series = Bolyai Society Mathematical Studies | title = Horizons of combinatorics | volume = 17 | year = 2008| citeseerx = 10.1.1.222.5699 | isbn = 978-3-540-77199-9 }}. See in particular Theorem 2.1, [https://books.google.com/books?id=kIKW18ENfUMC&pg=PA192 pp. 192–193].</ref> ===Category theory=== Several results in [[category theory]] invoke the axiom of choice for their proof. These results might be weaker than, equivalent to, or stronger than the axiom of choice, depending on the strength of the technical foundations. For example, if one defines categories in terms of sets, that is, as sets of objects and morphisms (usually called a [[small category]]), then there is no [[category of sets|category of all sets]], and so it is difficult for a category-theoretic formulation to apply to all sets. On the other hand, other foundational descriptions of category theory are considerably stronger, and an identical category-theoretic statement of choice may be stronger than the standard formulation, à la class theory, mentioned above. Examples of category-theoretic statements which require choice include: *Every small [[category (mathematics)|category]] has a [[skeleton (category theory)|skeleton]]. *If two small categories are weakly equivalent, then they are [[equivalence of categories|equivalent]]. *Every continuous functor on a small-complete category which satisfies the appropriate solution set condition has a [[adjoint functors|left-adjoint]] (the Freyd adjoint functor theorem). ==Weaker forms== There are several weaker statements that are not equivalent to the axiom of choice but are closely related. One example is the [[axiom of dependent choice]] (DC). A still weaker example is the [[axiom of countable choice]] (AC<sub>ω</sub> or CC), which states that a choice function exists for any countable set of nonempty sets. These axioms are sufficient for many proofs in elementary [[mathematical analysis]], and are consistent with some principles, such as the Lebesgue measurability of all sets of reals, that are disprovable from the full axiom of choice. Given an ordinal parameter α ≥ ω+2 — for every set ''S'' with rank less than α, ''S'' is well-orderable. Given an ordinal parameter α ≥ 1 — for every set ''S'' with [[Hartogs number]] less than ω<sub>α</sub>, ''S'' is well-orderable. As the ordinal parameter is increased, these approximate the full axiom of choice more and more closely. Other choice axioms weaker than axiom of choice include the [[Boolean prime ideal theorem]] and the [[Uniformization (set theory)|axiom of uniformization]]. The former is equivalent in ZF to [[Alfred Tarski|Tarski]]'s 1930 [[ultrafilter lemma]]: every [[Filter (set theory)|filter]] is a subset of some [[Ultrafilter (set theory)|ultrafilter]]. ===Results requiring AC (or weaker forms) but weaker than it===<!-- This section is linked from [[Basis (linear algebra)]] --> One of the most interesting aspects of the axiom of choice is the large number of places in mathematics where it shows up. Here are some statements that require the axiom of choice in the sense that they are not provable from ZF but are provable from ZFC (ZF plus AC). Equivalently, these statements are true in all models of ZFC but false in some models of ZF. *[[Set theory]] **The [[ultrafilter lemma]] (with ZF) can be used to prove the Axiom of choice for finite sets: Given <math>I \neq \varnothing</math> and a collection <math>\left(X_i\right)_{i \in I}</math> of non-empty {{em|finite}} sets, their product <math>\prod_{i \in I} X_{i}</math> is not empty.<ref name="Muger2020">{{cite book|last=Muger|first= Michael|title=Topology for the Working Mathematician|year=2020}}</ref> **The [[union (set theory)|union]] of any countable family of [[countable sets]] is countable (this requires [[Axiom of countable choice|countable choice]] but not the full axiom of choice). **If the set ''A'' is [[infinite set|infinite]], then there exists an [[injective function|injection]] from the [[natural number]]s '''N''' to ''A'' (see [[Dedekind infinite]]).<ref>It is shown by {{harvnb|Jech|2008|pp=119–131}}, that the axiom of countable choice implies the equivalence of infinite and Dedekind-infinite sets, but that the equivalence of infinite and Dedekind-infinite sets does not imply the axiom of countable choice in ZF.</ref> **Eight definitions of a [[finite set#Other concepts of finiteness|finite set]] are equivalent.<ref>It was shown by {{harvnb|Lévy|1958}} and others using Mostowski models that eight definitions of a finite set are independent in ZF without AC, although they are equivalent when AC is assumed. The definitions are I-finite, Ia-finite, II-finite, III-finite, IV-finite, V-finite, VI-finite and VII-finite. I-finiteness is the same as normal finiteness. IV-finiteness is the same as Dedekind-finiteness.</ref> **Every infinite [[determinacy#Basic notions|game]] <math>G_S</math> in which <math>S</math> is a [[Borel set|Borel]] subset of [[Baire space (set theory)|Baire space]] is [[determinacy#Basic notions|determined]]. * Every infinite [[cardinal number|cardinal]] ''κ'' satisfies 2×''κ'' = ''κ''.<ref>{{cite journal|last=Sageev|first=Gershon|title=An independence result concerning the axiom of choice|journal=Annals of Mathematical Logic|volume=8|issue=1–2|date=March 1975|pages=1–184|doi=10.1016/0003-4843(75)90002-9}}</ref> *[[Measure theory]] **The [[Vitali set|Vitali theorem]] on the existence of [[non-measurable set]]s, which states that there exists a subset of the [[real numbers]] that is not [[Lebesgue measurable]]. **There exist Lebesgue-measurable subsets of the real numbers that are not [[Borel set]]s. That is, the Borel σ-algebra on the real numbers (which is generated by all real intervals) is strictly included the Lebesgue-measure σ-algebra on the real numbers. **The [[Hausdorff paradox]]. **The [[Banach–Tarski paradox]]. *[[Algebra]] **Every [[field (mathematics)|field]] has an [[algebraic closure]]. **Every [[field extension]] has a [[transcendence basis]]. **Every infinite-dimensional [[vector space]] contains an infinite linearly independent subset (this requires [[Axiom of dependent choice|dependent choice]], but not the full axiom of choice). **[[Stone's representation theorem for Boolean algebras]] needs the [[Boolean prime ideal theorem]]. **The [[Nielsen–Schreier theorem]], that every subgroup of a free group is free. **The additive groups of '''[[real numbers|R]]''' and '''[[complex number|C]]''' are isomorphic.<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.cs.nyu.edu/pipermail/fom/2006-February/009959.html|title=[FOM] Are (C,+) and (R,+) isomorphic|date=21 February 2006 }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal|title=A consequence of the axiom of choice|first=C. J.|last=Ash|journal=Journal of the Australian Mathematical Society|year=1975 |volume=19 |issue=3 |pages=306–308 |doi=10.1017/S1446788700031505 |s2cid=122334025 |doi-access=free}}</ref> *[[Functional analysis]] **The [[Hahn–Banach theorem]] in [[functional analysis]], allowing the extension of [[linear map|linear functionals]]. **The theorem that every [[Hilbert space]] has an orthonormal basis. **The [[Banach–Alaoglu theorem]] about [[compactness]] of sets of functionals. **The [[Baire category theorem]] about [[complete space|complete]] [[metric space]]s, and its consequences, such as the [[open mapping theorem (functional analysis)|open mapping theorem]] and the [[closed graph theorem]]. **On every infinite-dimensional topological vector space there is a [[discontinuous linear map]]. *[[General topology]] **A uniform space is compact if and only if it is complete and totally bounded. **Every [[Tychonoff space]] has a [[Stone–Čech compactification]]. *[[Mathematical logic]] **[[Gödel's completeness theorem]] for first-order logic: every consistent set of first-order sentences has a completion. That is, every consistent set of first-order sentences can be extended to a maximal consistent set. **The [[compactness theorem]]: If <math>\Sigma</math> is a set of [[First-order predicate calculus|first-order]] (or alternatively, [[Propositional calculus|zero-order]]) [[Sentence (mathematical logic)|sentences]] such that every [[Finite set|finite]] subset of <math>\Sigma</math> has a [[Model (model theory)|model]], then <math>\Sigma</math> has a model.{{sfn|Schechter|1996|pp=391-392}} ===Possibly equivalent implications of AC=== There are several historically important set-theoretic statements implied by AC whose equivalence to AC is open. Zermelo cited the partition principle, which was formulated before AC itself, as a justification for believing AC. In 1906, Russell declared PP to be equivalent, but whether the partition principle implies AC is the oldest open problem in set theory,<ref>{{cite web | url=https://karagila.org/2014/on-the-partition-principle/ | title=On the Partition Principle }}</ref> and the equivalences of the other statements are similarly hard old open problems. In every ''known'' model of ZF where choice fails, these statements fail too, but it is unknown whether they can hold without choice. *[[Set theory]] **Partition principle: if there is a [[Surjective function|surjection]] from ''A'' to ''B'', there is an [[Injective function|injection]] from ''B'' to ''A''. Equivalently, every [[Partition of a set|partition]] ''P'' of a set ''S'' is less than or equal to ''S'' in size. **Converse [[Schröder–Bernstein theorem]]: if two sets have surjections to each other, they are equinumerous. **Weak partition principle: if there is an [[Injective function|injection]] and a [[Surjective function|surjection]] from ''A'' to ''B'', then ''A'' and ''B'' are equinumerous. Equivalently, a partition of a set ''S'' cannot be strictly larger than ''S''. If WPP holds, this already implies the existence of a non-measurable set. Each of the previous three statements is implied by the preceding one, but it is unknown if any of these implications can be reversed. **There is no infinite decreasing sequence of cardinals. The equivalence was conjectured by Schoenflies in 1905. *[[Abstract algebra]] **[[Hahn embedding theorem]]: Every ordered abelian group ''G'' order-embeds as a subgroup of the additive group <math>\mathbb{R}^\Omega</math> endowed with a [[lexicographical order]], where Ω is the set of Archimedean equivalence classes of ''G''. This equivalence was conjectured by Hahn in 1907. ==Stronger forms of the negation of AC== If we abbreviate by BP the claim that every set of real numbers has the [[property of Baire]], then BP is stronger than ¬AC, which asserts the nonexistence of any choice function on perhaps only a single set of nonempty sets. Strengthened negations may be compatible with weakened forms of AC. For example, ZF + DC<ref>[[Axiom of dependent choice]]</ref> + BP is consistent, if ZF is. It is also consistent with ZF + DC that every set of reals is [[Lebesgue measurable]], but this consistency result, due to [[Robert M. Solovay]], cannot be proved in ZFC itself, but requires a mild [[large cardinal]] assumption (the existence of an [[inaccessible cardinal]]). The much stronger [[axiom of determinacy]], or AD, implies that every set of reals is Lebesgue measurable, has the property of Baire, and has the [[perfect set property]] (all three of these results are refuted by AC itself). ZF + DC + AD is consistent provided that a sufficiently strong large cardinal axiom is consistent (the existence of infinitely many [[Woodin cardinal]]s). [[Willard Van Orman Quine|Quine]]'s system of axiomatic set theory, [[New Foundations]] (NF), takes its name from the title ("New Foundations for Mathematical Logic") of the 1937 article that introduced it. In the NF axiomatic system, the axiom of choice can be disproved.<ref name="quinenf">{{cite encyclopedia|title=Quine's New Foundations|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/quine-nf/|encyclopedia=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|access-date=2017-11-10}}</ref> ==Statements implying the negation of AC== There are models of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory in which the axiom of choice is false. We shall abbreviate "Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory plus the negation of the axiom of choice" by ZF¬C. For certain models of ZF¬C, it is possible to validate the negation of some standard ZFC theorems. As any model of ZF¬C is also a model of ZF, it is the case that for each of the following statements, there exists a model of ZF in which that statement is true. *The negation of the [[Partition principle|weak partition principle]]: There is a set that can be partitioned into strictly more equivalence classes than the original set has elements, and a function whose domain is strictly smaller than its range. In fact, this is the case in all ''known'' models. *There is a function ''f'' from the real numbers to the real numbers such that ''f'' is not continuous at ''a'', but ''f'' is [[Sequential continuity|sequentially continuous]] at ''a'', i.e., for any sequence {''x<sub>n</sub>''} converging to ''a'', lim<sub>''n''</sub> f(''x<sub>n</sub>'')=f(a). *There is an infinite set of real numbers without a countably infinite subset. *The real numbers are a countable union of countable sets.<ref>{{harvnb|Jech|2008|pp=142–144}}, Theorem 10.6 with proof.</ref> This does not imply that the real numbers are countable: As pointed out above, to show that a countable union of countable sets is itself countable requires the [[Axiom of countable choice]]. *There is a field with no algebraic closure. *In all models of ZF¬C there is a vector space with no basis. *There is a vector space with two bases of different cardinalities. *There is a free [[complete Boolean algebra]] on countably many generators.<ref name="Stavi, 1974">{{cite journal| first= Jonathan | last=Stavi| year=1974 |title=A model of ZF with an infinite free complete Boolean algebra| journal=[[Israel Journal of Mathematics]]| volume=20| issue= 2| pages=149–163|doi=10.1007/BF02757883|doi-access=| s2cid=119543439}}</ref> *There is [[Amorphous set|a set that cannot be linearly ordered]]. *There exists a model of ZF¬C in which every set in R<sup>''n''</sup> is [[measurable]]. Thus it is possible to exclude counterintuitive results like the [[Banach–Tarski paradox]] which are provable in ZFC. Furthermore, this is possible whilst assuming the [[Axiom of dependent choice]], which is weaker than AC but sufficient to develop most of [[real analysis]]. *In all models of ZF¬C, the [[generalized continuum hypothesis]] does not hold. For proofs, see {{harvtxt|Jech|2008}}. Additionally, by imposing definability conditions on sets (in the sense of [[descriptive set theory]]) one can often prove restricted versions of the axiom of choice from axioms incompatible with general choice. This appears, for example, in the [[Moschovakis coding lemma]]. == Axiom of choice in type theory == In [[type theory]], a different kind of statement is known as the axiom of choice. This form begins with two types, σ and τ, and a relation ''R'' between objects of type σ and objects of type τ. The axiom of choice states that if for each ''x'' of type σ there exists a ''y'' of type τ such that ''R''(''x'',''y''), then there is a function ''f'' from objects of type σ to objects of type τ such that ''R''(''x'',''f''(''x'')) holds for all ''x'' of type σ: :<math> (\forall x^\sigma)(\exists y^\tau) R(x,y) \to (\exists f^{\sigma \to \tau})(\forall x^\sigma) R(x,f(x)). </math> Unlike in set theory, the axiom of choice in type theory is typically stated as an [[axiom scheme]], in which ''R'' varies over all formulas or over all formulas of a particular logical form. ==Notes== {{Reflist}} ==References== *{{cite journal | last1 = Blass | first1 = Andreas | date = 1979 | title = Injectivity, Projectivity and the Axiom of Choice | journal = Transactions of the American Mathematical Society | volume = 255 | pages = 31–59 | doi = 10.2307/1998165 | jstor = 1998165 | doi-access= free }} * {{cite conference | last = Dawson | first = J. W. | title = Shaken Foundations or Groundbreaking Realignment? A Centennial Assessment of Kurt Gödel's Impact on Logic, Mathematics, and Computer Science | book-title = Proceedings of the 21st Annual IEEE Symposium on Logic in Computer Science (LICS 2006) | date = August 2006 | pages = 339–341 | doi = 10.1109/LICS.2006.47 | isbn = 978-0-7695-2631-7 | s2cid = 15526447 }} * {{citation|last=Fraenkel|first= Abraham|author-link=Abraham Fraenkel |title=Der Begriff "definit" und die Unabhängigkeit des Auswahlaxioms| jfm =48.0199.02 |journal=Sitzungsberichte der Königlich Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften|year= 1922|pages= 253–257 }} * {{cite book | last1 = Fraenkel | first1 = Abraham A. | author1-link = Abraham Fraenkel | last2 = Bar-Hillel | first2 = Yehoshua | author2-link = Yehoshua Bar-Hillel | last3 = Lévy | first3 = Azriel | author3-link = Azriel Lévy | edition = 2nd | location = Amsterdam-London | mr = 0345816 | pages = 69–70 | publisher = North-Holland Publishing Co. | title = Foundations of set theory | url = https://books.google.com/books?id=ah2bwOwc06MC&pg=PA69 | year = 1973| isbn = 9780080887050 }} *{{cite journal | last1 = Hajnal | first1 = A. | author1-link=András Hajnal | last2 = Kertész | first2 = A. | title = Some new algebraic equivalents of the axiom of choice | journal = Publ. Math. Debrecen | volume = 19 | year = 1972 | pages = 339–340 }} * {{cite book | last=Halmos | first=Paul R. | author-link=Paul Halmos | title=Naive Set Theory | series=The University Series in Undergraduate Mathematics | publisher=van Nostrand Company |location=Princeton, NJ| year=1960 | zbl=0087.04403| title-link=Naive Set Theory (book) }} * {{cite book |last=Herrlich |first=Horst | author-link=Horst Herrlich |title=Axiom of Choice |publisher=[[Springer Science+Business Media|Springer-Verlag]] |location=Berlin |year=2006 |series=Lecture Notes in Math. 1876 |isbn=978-3-540-30989-5}} * {{citation|last1=Howard|first1=Paul|last2=Rubin|first2=Jean E.|author2-link=Jean E. Rubin|title=Consequences of the axiom of choice|year=1998|publisher=[[American Mathematical Society]]|location=Providence, Rhode Island|series=Mathematical Surveys and Monographs|volume=59|isbn=9780821809778|url-access=registration|url=https://archive.org/details/consequencesofax0000howa}} * {{cite book | last = Jech | first = Thomas | author-link = Thomas Jech | isbn = 978-0-486-46624-8 | orig-year=1973 | publisher = [[Dover Publications]] | location = Mineola, New York | title = The axiom of choice | year = 2008}} * {{cite book|last=Jech|first=Thomas |author-link=Thomas Jech |chapter=About the Axiom of Choice |title=Handbook of Mathematical Logic |editor=John Barwise |year=1977}} * {{cite journal |last=Lévy |first=Azriel |author-link= Azriel Lévy|year=1958 |title=The independence of various definitions of finiteness |journal=[[Fundamenta Mathematicae]] |volume=46 |pages=1–13 |url= http://matwbn.icm.edu.pl/ksiazki/fm/fm46/fm4611.pdf |archive-url=https://ghostarchive.org/archive/20221009/http://matwbn.icm.edu.pl/ksiazki/fm/fm46/fm4611.pdf |archive-date=2022-10-09 |url-status=live|doi=10.4064/fm-46-1-1-13 |doi-access=free }} * {{cite book | last = Mac Lane | first = Saunders | author-link = Saunders Mac Lane | title = [[Mathematics, Form and Function]] | publisher = Springer-Verlag | year = 1986 | isbn = 0-387-96217-4}} * {{cite book | last = Martin-Löf | first = Per | author-link = Per Martin-Löf | chapter = 100 years of Zermelo's axiom of choice: What was the problem with it? | title = Logicism, Intuitionism, and Formalism: What Has Become of Them? | editor1-first = Sten | editor1-last = Lindström | editor2-first = Erik | editor2-last = Palmgren | editor3-first = Krister | editor3-last = Segerberg | editor4-first = Viggo | editor4-last = Stoltenberg-Hansen | year = 2008 | isbn = 1-4020-8925-2 }} * {{cite book |last=Mendelson|first=Elliott|author-link=Elliott Mendelson|title=Introduction to Mathematical Logic|year=1964|publisher=Van Nostrand Reinhold|location=New York}} * {{cite book|last1=Moore|first1=Gregory H.|title=Zermelo's axiom of choice, Its origins, development and influence|publisher=[[Springer Science+Business Media|Springer]]|year=1982|isbn=978-0-387-90670-6}}, available as a [[Dover Publications]] reprint, 2013, {{ISBN|0-486-48841-1}}. * {{citation|first= Andrzej |last=Mostowski|author-link=Andrzej Mostowski|title= Über den Begriff einer Endlichen Menge|year=1938|journal= Comptes Rendus des Séances de la Société des Sciences et des Lettres de Varsovie, Classe III|volume=31|issue=8|pages=13–20}} * {{cite book |last1=Moore|first1=Gregory H|title=Zermelo's axiom of choice: Its origins, development & influence|orig-year=1982|year=2013|publisher=Dover Publications|location=Mineola, New York|isbn=978-0-486-48841-7}} * {{cite book|title=An Invitation to Abstract Algebra|date=21 December 2021|publisher=CRC Press|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=KWlPEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA316|first=Steven|last=Rosenberg|isbn=9781000516333 }} * {{cite book|title=The Elements of Mathematical Logic|first=Paul C.|last=Rosenbloom|publisher=Courier Dover Publications|year=2005|isbn=9780486446172|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=089eY-s33EsC&pg=PA147}} * {{cite book | last1 = Rubin | first1 = Herman | author1-link=Herman Rubin | last2 = Rubin | first2 = Jean E. | author2-link=Jean E. Rubin | title = Equivalents of the Axiom of Choice | publisher = North Holland / Elsevier | date = April 1970| edition= 2nd print | orig-year = 1963 | isbn = 9780720422252 }} * {{cite book | last1 = Rubin | first1 = Herman | author1-link=Herman Rubin | last2 = Rubin | first2 = Jean E. | author2-link=Jean E. Rubin | title = Equivalents of the Axiom of Choice II | publisher = North Holland / Elsevier | date = July 1985 | isbn = 0-444-87708-8 }} * {{cite book |last1=Russell|first1=Bertrand|author1-link=Bertrand Russell|title=Introduction to mathematical philosophy|publisher=Dover Publications|location=New York|orig-year=1919|date=1993|isbn=978-0-486-27724-0}} * {{Schechter Handbook of Analysis and Its Foundations}} <!--{{sfn|Schechter|1996|p=}}--> * {{cite book|last1=Suppes|first1=Patrick|author1-link=Patrick Suppes|title=Axiomatic set theory|publisher=Dover|location=Mineola, New York|year=1972|orig-year=1960|isbn=978-0-486-61630-8|url-access=registration|url=https://archive.org/details/axiomaticsettheo00supp_0}} * {{cite book | last = Tourlakis | first = George | title = Lectures in Logic and Set Theory. Vol. II: Set Theory | publisher = [[Cambridge University Press]] | year = 2003 | isbn = 0-511-06659-7 }} * {{cite journal|last=Zermelo| first=Ernst | author-link = Ernst Zermelo| year=1904| url=http://gdz.sub.uni-goettingen.de/no_cache/en/dms/load/img/?IDDOC=28526 |format=reprint|title=Beweis, dass jede Menge wohlgeordnet werden kann| journal=Mathematische Annalen| volume=59| issue=4| pages=514–16|doi=10.1007/BF01445300| s2cid=124189935}} *{{cite journal | last = Zermelo | first = Ernst | author-link = Ernst Zermelo | title = Untersuchungen über die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre I | journal = Mathematische Annalen | volume = 65 | year = 1908 | pages = 261–281 | url = https://gdz.sub.uni-goettingen.de/id/PPN235181684_0065?tify=%7B%22view%22:%22info%22,%22pages%22:%5B271%5D%7D | format = PDF | access-date= 2025-05-15 }} ::Translated in: [[Jean van Heijenoort]], 2002. ''From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931''. New edition. [[Harvard University Press]]. {{ISBN|0-674-32449-8}} ::*1904. "Proof that every set can be well-ordered," 139-41. ::*1908. "Investigations in the foundations of set theory I," 199–215. ==External links== {{wikiquote}} *[https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php/Axiom_of_choice Axiom of Choice] entry in the Springer [[Encyclopedia of Mathematics]]. *[https://web.archive.org/web/20130801134743/http://www.apronus.com/provenmath/choice.htm Axiom of Choice and Its Equivalents] entry at ProvenMath. Includes formal statement of the Axiom of Choice, Hausdorff's Maximal Principle, Zorn's Lemma and formal proofs of their equivalence down to the finest detail. *[http://www.math.purdue.edu/~hrubin/JeanRubin/Papers/conseq.html Consequences of the Axiom of Choice] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210515021241/https://www.math.purdue.edu/~hrubin/JeanRubin/Papers/conseq.html |date=15 May 2021 }}, based on the book by [http://www.emunix.emich.edu/~phoward/ Paul Howard] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210226235056/https://emunix.emich.edu/~phoward/ |date=26 February 2021 }} and Jean Rubin. *{{SEP|axiom-choice|The Axiom of Choice|[[John Lane Bell]]}}. {{Set theory}} {{Mathematical logic}} {{Authority control}} {{DEFAULTSORT:Axiom of Choice}} [[Category:Axiom of choice| ]]
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Templates used on this page:
Template:About
(
edit
)
Template:Authority control
(
edit
)
Template:Blockquote
(
edit
)
Template:Citation
(
edit
)
Template:Cite book
(
edit
)
Template:Cite conference
(
edit
)
Template:Cite encyclopedia
(
edit
)
Template:Cite journal
(
edit
)
Template:Cite web
(
edit
)
Template:Em
(
edit
)
Template:Harvnb
(
edit
)
Template:Harvtxt
(
edit
)
Template:ISBN
(
edit
)
Template:Math theorem
(
edit
)
Template:Mathematical logic
(
edit
)
Template:Nlab
(
edit
)
Template:Nowrap
(
edit
)
Template:Redirect-distinguish
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)
Template:SEP
(
edit
)
Template:Schechter Handbook of Analysis and Its Foundations
(
edit
)
Template:See also
(
edit
)
Template:Set theory
(
edit
)
Template:Sfn
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)
Template:Use dmy dates
(
edit
)
Template:Webarchive
(
edit
)
Template:Wikiquote
(
edit
)
Search
Search
Editing
Axiom of choice
Add topic