Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Paul Feyerabend
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
====Empiricism, pluralism, and incommensurability==== Much of Feyerabend's work from the late 1950s until the late 1960s was devoted to methodological issues in science. Specifically, Feyerabend offers several criticisms of [[empiricism]] and offers his own brand of theoretical pluralism. One such criticism concerns the distinction between observational and theoretical terms. If an observational term is understood as one whose acceptance can be determined by immediate perception, then what counts as 'observational' or 'theoretical' changes throughout history as our patterns of habituation change and our ability to directly perceive entities evolve.<ref name=PKF19601>{{cite journal|last=Feyerabend |first=Paul |title= Das Problem der Existenz theoretischer Entitäten |journal= Probleme der Wissenschaftstheorie: Festschrift für Viktor Kraft |date=1960|pages=16}}</ref> On another definition, observation terms are those that can be known directly and with certainty whereas theoretical terms are hypothetical. Feyerabend argues that all statements are hypothetical, since the act of observation requires theories to justify its veridicality.<ref name=PKF19602>{{cite journal|last=Feyerabend |first=Paul |title= Das Problem der Existenz theoretischer Entitäten |journal= Probleme der Wissenschaftstheorie: Festschrift für Viktor Kraft |date=1960|pages=21}}</ref> To replace empiricism, Feyerabend advances theoretical pluralism as a methodological rule for scientific progress. On this view, proliferating new theories increases the testability of previous theories that might be well-established by observations. This is because some tests cannot be unearthed without the invention of an alternative theory.<ref name=PKF1963>{{cite journal|last=Feyerabend |first=Paul |title= How to Be a Good Empiricist: A Plea for Tolerance in Matters Epistemological |journal= Philosophy of Science: The Delaware Seminar Volume 2|date=1963|pages=3–39}}</ref> One example Feyerabend uses repeatedly is [[Brownian motion]] which was not a test of the [[second law of thermodynamics|second law of classical thermodynamics]].<ref>{{cite journal | last=Feyerabend | first=Paul K. | date=1962 | title=Explanation, reduction, and empiricism | series=Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science | journal=Scientific Explanation, Space & Time | editor1-first=H. | editor1-last=Feigl | editor2-first=G. | editor2-last=Maxwell | location=Minneapolis | volume=3 | pages=72|hdl = 11299/184633|hdl-access=free}}</ref> To become a test, it must be first explained by an alternative theory – namely, Einstein's [[kinetic theory of gases]] – which formally contradicts the accepted theory. By proliferating new theories, we increase the number of indirect tests of our theories. This makes theoretical pluralism central to Feyerabend's conception of scientific method. Eventually, Feyerabend's pluralism incorporates what he calls the "principle of tenacity."<ref name=PKF1968>{{cite journal|last=Feyerabend |first=Paul |title= Outline of a Pluralistic Theory of Knowledge and Action |journal= Planning for Diversity and Choice |date=1968|pages=107}}</ref> The principle of tenacity allows scientists to pursue theories regardless of the problems it may possess. Examples of problems might include recalcitrant evidence, [[paradox|theoretical paradoxes]], [[computational complexity|mathematical complexity]], or [[inconsistency]] with neighboring theories. Feyerabend learned of this idea from Kuhn, who argued that without tenacity all theories would have been prematurely abandoned.<ref name=PHH>{{cite journal|last=Hoyningen-Huene |first=Paul |title= Two letters of Paul Feyerabend to Thomas S. Kuhn on a draft of the structure of scientific revolutions |journal= Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A |date=1995| volume=26|issue=3|pages= 353–387|doi=10.1016/0039-3681(95)00005-8 |bibcode=1995SHPSA..26..353H }}</ref> This principle complements the "principle of proliferation", which admonishes us to invent as many theories as possible, so that those invented theories can become plausible rivals.<ref name=Shaw2017>{{cite journal|last=Shaw |first=Jamie|title= Was Feyerabend an Anarchist? The Structure(s) of 'Anything Goes'|journal= Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A|volume=64|date=2017| pages= 11–21|doi=10.1016/j.shpsa.2017.06.002 |pmid=29042018 |bibcode=2017SHPSA..64...11S }}</ref> In his "Empiricism, Reduction, and Experience" (1962), Feyerabend outlines his theory of incommensurability. His theory appears in the same year as Thomas Kuhn's discussion of incommensurability in ''[[The Structure of Scientific Revolutions]]'', but the two were developed independently.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/incommensurability/|title=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|first1=Eric|last1=Oberheim|first2=Paul|last2=Hoyningen-Huene|editor-first=Edward N.|editor-last=Zalta|date=February 1, 2018|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|via=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy}}</ref> According to Feyerabend, some instances of theory change in the history of science do not involve a successor theory that retains its predecessor as a [[Limiting case (philosophy of science)|limiting case]]. In other words, scientific progress does not always involve producing a theory that is a [[inductive reasoning|generalization]] of the previous theory. This is because the successor theory is formally inconsistent with the previous theory attempting to explain the same domain of phenomena.<ref name="Feyerabend 1962 28–97">{{cite journal | last=Feyerabend | first=Paul K. | date=1962 | title=Explanation, reduction, and empiricism | series=Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science | journal=Scientific Explanation, Space & Time | editor1-first=H. | editor1-last=Feigl | editor2-first=G. | editor2-last=Maxwell | location=Minneapolis | volume=3 | pages=28–97|hdl = 11299/184633|hdl-access=free}}</ref> Moreover, the two theories do not share the same [[empirical evidence|empirical content]] and, therefore, cannot be compared by the same set of observation statements. For example, [[Jean Buridan|Buridan]]'s [[theory of impetus|impetus principle]] has no analogue in [[classical mechanics]]. The closest analogue would be [[momentum]], but the two notions are qualitatively distinct (impetus causes motion whereas momentum is the result of motion). Furthermore, Feyerabend claims that there can be no 'parallel notion' of impetus that is explicable within classical mechanics. Any parallel notion that gives non-zero values must assume that inertial movements happen in a resisting medium, which is inconsistent with the assumption in classical mechanics that inertial motion happens in empty space. Therefore, "the concept of impetus, as fixed by the usage established in the impetus theory, cannot be defined in a reasonable way within Newton's theory [since] the usage involves laws... which are inconsistent with Newtonian physics."<ref>{{cite journal | last=Feyerabend | first=Paul K. | date=1962 | title=Explanation, reduction, and empiricism | series=Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science | journal=Scientific Explanation, Space & Time | editor1-first=H. | editor1-last=Feigl | editor2-first=G. | editor2-last=Maxwell | location=Minneapolis | volume=3 | pages=66|hdl = 11299/184633|hdl-access=free}}</ref> In response to criticisms of Feyerabend's position, he clarifies that there are other ways in which theories can be compared such as comparing the structures of infinite sets of elements to detect [[isomorphism]]s,{{sfn|Feyerabend|1965|pp=102-103}} comparing "local grammars" ,{{sfn|Feyerabend|1965|loc=fn.32 116}} or building a [[model]] of a theory within its alternative.{{sfn|Feyerabend|1965|p=115}} Incommensurability, however, only arises if scientists make the choice to interpret theories [[scientific realism|realistically]]. Theories interpreted [[instrumentalism|instrumentally]] cannot be incommensurable, on Feyerabend's view. Feyerabend's pluralism is supported by what he calls the 'pragmatic theory of meaning' which he developed in his dissertation.<ref name="Kuby"/> Here, he explicitly resuscitates Neurath and Carnap's [[physicalism]] from the 1930s. According to the pragmatic theory of meaning, language consists of two parts. First, there is the characteristic of a language which is a series of noises produced under specific experimental situations. On Feyerabend's views, human observation has no special epistemic status – it is just another kind of measuring apparatus. The characteristic of a language comes from placing observers in the presence of phenomena and instructing them to make specific noises when a phenomenon is sensed. These noises, to become statements (or parts of a language with [[meaning (linguistic)|meaning]]), must then be [[language interpretation|interpreted]]. Interpretation comes from a theory, whose meaning is given is learned though not necessarily through ostension.<ref name=PKF1958>{{cite journal|last=Feyerabend |first=Paul |title= An Attempt at a Realistic Interpretation of Experience |journal= Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society|volume=58|date=1958|pages=143–170|doi=10.1093/aristotelian/58.1.143 }}</ref> Once we have an interpreted characteristic, we have statements that can be used to test theories.
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Paul Feyerabend
(section)
Add topic