Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Derek Parfit
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Population ethics and future generations== === Non-identity problem === The [[non-identity problem]] arises from the observation that actions taken today can fundamentally alter which future people come into existence. In chapter 16 of ''Reasons and Persons'', Parfit posits that one's existence is intimately related to the time and conditions of one's conception.<ref name=":4" />{{Rp|351}} He calls this "The Time-Dependence Claim": "If any particular person had not been conceived when he was in fact conceived, it is in fact true that he would never have existed".<ref name=":4" />{{Rp|351}} Like the [[butterfly effect]] in [[chaos theory]], small changes in initial conditions can have profound downstream effects on human reproduction. Actions may not just affect the welfare of future individuals, but also cause different individuals to be born.<ref>{{Cite web |title=The Nonidentity Problem |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/nonidentity-problem/ |website=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy}}</ref> If the moral ramifications of potential policies are considered in [[Person-affecting view|person-affecting]] terms, there is no reason to prefer a sound policy over an unsound one, provided that its effects are not felt by the next few generations.<ref>{{Cite web |date=2017-06-12 |title=Should we take ethical account of people who do not yet exist? |url=https://aeon.co/essays/should-we-take-ethical-account-of-people-who-do-not-yet-exist |access-date=2025-01-26 |website=Aeon |language=en}}</ref> Parfit eventually became convinced that personal identity is irrelevant to ethics.<ref name=":6">{{Cite web |last=Matthews |first=Dylan |date=2017-01-03 |title=The whole philosophy community is mourning Derek Parfit. Here’s why he mattered. |url=https://www.vox.com/science-and-health/2017/1/3/14148208/derek-parfit-rip-obit |access-date=2025-01-26 |website=Vox |language=en-US}}</ref> He wrote about an article in ''[[The Times]]'' in which a politician praised a recent decline in teenage pregnancy. A man wrote a letter saying he had had a teenage mother and, although the early years had been hard, he now had a life thoroughly worth living. The man asked whether the politician was suggesting it would have been better if he had never been born. Parfit said the man would waive the right to have such-and-such level of a good start in life merely to exist. He wrote, "The objection must be that if she had waited, she could have given to some other child a better start in life."<ref>[https://rintintin.colorado.edu/~vancecd/phil308/Parfit1.pdf “The Non-Identity Problem,”] from the book ''Reasons and Persons'', Derek Parfit, please see page 11 in this excerpt.</ref> === Mere addition paradox and repugnant conclusion === In part four of ''Reasons and Persons'', Parfit discusses possible futures for the world.<ref name=":4" />{{Rp|349–441}} He discusses possible futures and population growth in chapter 17, and argues that both [[average and total utilitarianism]] result in unwelcome conclusions when applied to population.<ref name=":4" />{{Rp|388}} In the section titled "Overpopulation", Parfit distinguishes between average utilitarianism and total utilitarianism. He formulates average utilitarianism in two ways. One is what Parfit calls the "Impersonal Average Principle", which he formulates as "If other things are equal, the best outcome is the one in which people's lives go, on average, best."<ref name=":4" />{{Rp|386}} The other is what he calls the "Hedonistic version"; he formulates this as "If other things are equal, the best outcome is the one in which there is the greatest average net sum of happiness, per life lived."<ref name=":4" />{{Rp|386}} Parfit then gives two formulations of the total utilitarianism view. The first formulation Parfit calls the "Hedonistic version of the Impersonal Total Principle": "If other things are equal, the best outcome is the one in which there would be the greatest quantity of happiness—the greatest net sum of happiness minus misery."<ref name=":4" />{{Rp|387}} He then describes the other formulation, the "non-Hedonistic Impersonal Total Principle": "If other things are equal, the best outcome is the one in which there would be the greatest quantity of whatever makes life worth living."<ref name=":4" />{{Rp|387}} [[File:MereAddition.svg|thumb|The width of each bar represents the size of a population, and the height represents the individual welfare level. The [[Mere addition paradox|mere addition]] from A to B results in a larger population with a lower individual welfare.]] [[File:RepugnantConclusion.svg|thumb|The "repugnant conclusion" involves repeating the mere addition until obtaining a much larger population Z with only slightly positive individual welfare.]] Applying total utilitarian standards (absolute total happiness) to possible population growth and welfare leads to what he calls the [[repugnant conclusion]]: "For any possible population of at least ten billion people, all with a very high quality of life, there must be some much larger imaginable population whose existence, if other things are equal, would be better, even though its members have lives that are barely worth living."<ref name=":4" />{{Rp|388}} Parfit illustrates this with a simple thought experiment: imagine a choice between two possible futures. In A, 10 billion people would live during the next generation, all with extremely happy lives, lives far happier than anyone's today. In B, there are 20 billion people all living lives that, while slightly less happy than those in A, are still very happy. Under total utility maximisation we should prefer B to A. Therefore, through a regressive process of population increases and happiness decreases (in each pair of cases the happiness decrease is outweighed by the population increase) we are forced to prefer Z, a world of hundreds of billions of people all living lives barely worth living, to A. Even if we do not hold that coming to exist can benefit someone, we still must at least admit that Z is no worse than A.<ref name=":6" /> Parfit and other philosophers have explored a number of potential ways to avoid this "repugnant conclusion", many of which are discussed in ''Reasons and Persons''. Parfit himself spent significant time trying to find a coherent ethical theory that would avoid it.<ref name=":6" /> One potential objection challenges what life in the A-world would be like and whether life in the Z-world would differ very much from a normal privileged life. Another one proposes that movement from the A-world to the Z-world can be blocked by discontinuity. [[Negative utilitarianism|Negative utilitarians]] may reject the premise of maximizing happiness, emphasizing the converse, the minimization of suffering.<ref name=":8" /> Philosopher [[Larry Temkin]] challenges the assumption that the "better than" relation is [[Transitive relation|transitive]].<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Temkin |first=Larry S. |date=1987 |title=Intransitivity and the Mere Addition Paradox |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/TEMIAT |journal=Philosophy and Public Affairs |volume=16 |issue=2 |pages=138–187}}</ref> Others proposed a minimal threshold of liberties and primary social goods to be distributed, or suggested to adopt a [[Deontology|deontological]] approach that looks to values and their transmission through time.<ref name=":8">Various authors of essays in ''The Repugnant Conclusion,'' eds. Jesper Ryberg and [[Torbjörn Tännsjö]] ([[Kluwer Academic Publishers]], 2004) {{ISBN|978-1402024726}}; and, Young Kim, [https://rowman.com/ISBN/9781498516518/Justice-as-Right-Actions-An-Original-Theory-of-Justice-in-Conversation-with-Major-Contemporary-Accounts Justice as Right Actions: An Original Theory of Justice in Conversation with Major Contemporary Accounts] ([[Rowman & Littlefield|Lexington Books]], 2015) ch.10 ( {{ISBN|978-1-4985-1651-8}}).</ref> [[Michael Huemer]] and [[Torbjörn Tännsjö]] endorse the conclusion, considering that the repugnance comes from intuitions that should be revised.<ref>{{Cite web |last=Matthews |first=Dylan |date=2019-06-05 |title=The case for adding more and more people to the Earth |url=https://www.vox.com/the-highlight/2019/6/5/18617894/repugnant-conclusion-population-growth-philosophy |access-date=2025-01-26 |website=Vox |language=en-US}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Huemer |first=Michael |date=2008 |title=In Defence of Repugnance |url=https://philarchive.org/archive/HUEIDO |journal=Mind}}</ref> In 2021, a number of philosophers said that avoiding the repugnant conclusion was receiving excessive focus and should not be considered a necessary condition for an adequate theory of [[population ethics]].<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Zuber |first=Stéphane |last2=Venkatesh |first2=Nikhil |last3=Tännsjö |first3=Torbjörn |last4=Tarsney |first4=Christian |last5=Stefánsson |first5=H. Orri |last6=Steele |first6=Katie |last7=Spears |first7=Dean |last8=Sebo |first8=Jeff |last9=Pivato |first9=Marcus |last10=Ord |first10=Toby |last11=Ng |first11=Yew-Kwang |last12=Masny |first12=Michal |last13=MacAskill |first13=William |last14=Lawson |first14=Nicholas |last15=Kuruc |first15=Kevin |date=13 April 2021 |title=What Should We Agree on about the Repugnant Conclusion? |url=https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/utilitas/article/what-should-we-agree-on-about-the-repugnant-conclusion/EB52C686BAFEF490CE37043A0A3DD075 |journal=Utilitas |language=en |volume=33 |issue=4 |pages=379–383 |doi=10.1017/S095382082100011X |issn=0953-8208|hdl=10852/90849 |hdl-access=free }}</ref> Against average utilitarianism, Parfit also argues that if all that matters is average happiness, then the best population could be arbitrarily small, for example containing only a few extremely happy individuals. Moreover, this would imply that adding people with lives worth living would make the world worse if these are less happy than the average.<ref name=":4" />{{Rp|420}}
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Derek Parfit
(section)
Add topic