Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Universal property
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Properties== ===Existence and uniqueness=== Defining a quantity does not guarantee its existence. Given a functor <math>F: \mathcal{C} \to \mathcal{D}</math> and an object <math>X</math> of <math>\mathcal{D}</math>, there may or may not exist a universal morphism from <math>X</math> to <math>F</math>. If, however, a universal morphism <math>(A, u)</math> does exist, then it is essentially unique. Specifically, it is unique [[up to]] a ''unique'' [[isomorphism]]: if <math>(A', u')</math> is another pair, then there exists a unique isomorphism <math>k: A \to A'</math> such that <math>u' = F(k) \circ u</math>. This is easily seen by substituting <math>(A, u')</math> in the definition of a universal morphism. It is the pair <math>(A, u)</math> which is essentially unique in this fashion. The object <math>A</math> itself is only unique up to isomorphism. Indeed, if <math>(A, u)</math> is a universal morphism and <math>k: A \to A'</math> is any isomorphism then the pair <math>(A', u')</math>, where <math>u' = F(k) \circ u</math> is also a universal morphism. ===Equivalent formulations=== The definition of a universal morphism can be rephrased in a variety of ways. Let <math>F: \mathcal{C} \to \mathcal{D}</math> be a functor and let <math>X</math> be an object of <math>\mathcal{D}</math>. Then the following statements are equivalent: * <math>(A, u)</math> is a universal morphism from <math>X</math> to <math>F</math> * <math>(A, u)</math> is an [[initial object]] of the [[comma category]] <math>(X \downarrow F)</math> * <math>(A, F(\bullet)\circ u)</math> is a [[representable functor|representation]] of <math>\text{Hom}_\mathcal{D}(X, F(-))</math>, where its components <math>(F(\bullet)\circ u)_B:\text{Hom}_{\mathcal{C}}(A, B) \to \text{Hom}_{\mathcal{D}}(X, F(B))</math> are defined by <math display="block">(F(\bullet)\circ u)_B(f:A\to B):X\to F(B) = F(f)\circ u:X\to F(B)</math> for each object <math>B</math> in <math>\mathcal{C}.</math> The dual statements are also equivalent: * <math>(A, u)</math> is a universal morphism from <math>F</math> to <math>X</math> * <math>(A, u)</math> is a [[terminal object]] of the comma category <math>(F \downarrow X)</math> * <math>(A, u\circ F(\bullet))</math> is a representation of <math>\text{Hom}_\mathcal{D}(F(-), X)</math>, where its components <math>(u\circ F(\bullet))_B:\text{Hom}_{\mathcal{C}}(B, A)\to \text{Hom}_{\mathcal{D}}(F(B), X)</math> are defined by <math display="block"> (u\circ F(\bullet))_B(f:B\to A):F(B)\to X = u\circ F(f):F(B)\to X</math> for each object <math>B</math> in <math>\mathcal{C}.</math> ===Relation to adjoint functors=== Suppose <math>(A_1, u_1)</math> is a universal morphism from <math>X_1</math> to <math>F</math> and <math>(A_2, u_2)</math> is a universal morphism from <math>X_2</math> to <math>F</math>. By the universal property of universal morphisms, given any morphism <math>h: X_1 \to X_2</math> there exists a unique morphism <math>g: A_1 \to A_2 </math> such that the following diagram commutes: [[File:Connection between universal elements inducing a functor.svg|center|Universal morphisms can behave like a natural transformation between functors under suitable conditions.]] If ''every'' object <math>X_i</math> of <math>\mathcal{D}</math> admits a universal morphism to <math>F</math>, then the assignment <math>X_i \mapsto A_i</math> and <math>h \mapsto g</math> defines a functor <math>G: \mathcal{D} \to \mathcal{C}</math>. The maps <math>u_i</math> then define a [[natural transformation]] from <math>1_\mathcal{D}</math> (the identity functor on <math>\mathcal{D}</math>) to <math>F\circ G</math>. The functors <math>(F, G)</math> are then a pair of [[adjoint functor]]s, with <math>G</math> left-adjoint to <math>F</math> and <math>F</math> right-adjoint to <math>G</math>. Similar statements apply to the dual situation of terminal morphisms from <math>F</math>. If such morphisms exist for every <math>X</math> in <math>\mathcal{C}</math> one obtains a functor <math>G: \mathcal{C} \to \mathcal{D}</math> which is right-adjoint to <math>F</math> (so <math>F</math> is left-adjoint to <math>G</math>). Indeed, all pairs of adjoint functors arise from universal constructions in this manner. Let <math>F</math> and <math>G</math> be a pair of adjoint functors with unit <math>\eta</math> and co-unit <math>\epsilon</math> (see the article on [[adjoint functors]] for the definitions). Then we have a universal morphism for each object in <math>\mathcal{C}</math> and <math>\mathcal{D}</math>: *For each object <math>X</math> in <math>\mathcal{C}</math>, <math>(F(X), \eta_X)</math> is a universal morphism from <math>X</math> to <math>G</math>. That is, for all <math>f: X \to G(Y)</math> there exists a unique <math>g: F(X) \to Y</math> for which the following diagrams commute. *For each object <math>Y</math> in <math>\mathcal{D}</math>, <math>(G(Y), \epsilon_Y)</math> is a universal morphism from <math>F</math> to <math>Y</math>. That is, for all <math>g: F(X) \to Y</math> there exists a unique <math>f: X \to G(Y)</math> for which the following diagrams commute. [[File:Universal morphisms appear as the unit and counit of adjunctions.svg|center|The unit and counit of an adjunction, which are natural transformations between functors, are an important example of universal morphisms.]] Universal constructions are more general than adjoint functor pairs: a universal construction is like an optimization problem; it gives rise to an adjoint pair if and only if this problem has a solution for every object of <math>\mathcal{C}</math> (equivalently, every object of <math>\mathcal{D}</math>).
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Universal property
(section)
Add topic