Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Justice
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Theories== {{further|Justice (virtue)|Cardinal virtues}} [[File:Bonino da Campione, Justice, c. 1357, NGA 46013.jpg|thumb|Bonino da Campione, ''Justice'', {{circa|1357}}, [[National Gallery of Art]]]]It has been said<ref>See, e.g., Eric Heinze, ''The Concept of Injustice'' (Routledge, 2013), pp. 4β10, 50β60.</ref> that 'systematic' or 'programmatic' political and moral philosophy in the West begins, in [[Plato]]'s [[Plato Republic|Republic]], with the question, 'What is Justice?'<ref>Plato, ''The Republic'', Book I, 331bβc.</ref> According to most contemporary theories of justice, justice is overwhelmingly important: [[John Rawls]] claims that "Justice is the first virtue of social institutions, as truth is of systems of thought."{{sfn|Rawls|1999|p=3}} In classical approaches, evident from [[Plato]] through to [[John Rawls|Rawls]], the concept of 'justice' is always construed in logical or 'etymological' opposition to the concept of injustice. Such approaches cite various examples of injustice, as problems which a theory of justice must overcome. A number of post-World War II approaches do, however, challenge that seemingly obvious dualism between those two concepts.<ref>*See, e.g., Eric Heinze, ''The Concept of Injustice'' ([[Routledge]], 2013). * Clive Barnett ''The Priority of Injustice: Locating Democracy in Critical Theory''</ref> Justice can be thought of as distinct from [[wikt:benevolence|benevolence]], [[Charity (virtue)|charity]], [[prudence (virtue)|prudence]], [[mercy]], [[generosity]], or [[compassion]], although these dimensions are regularly understood to also be interlinked. Justice is one of the [[cardinal virtue]]s.<ref>{{cite web |title=The Fourfold Virtues of Augustine & Plato & Confucius |url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160304074259/http://www.theplatonist.com/cardinal_virtues.htm |website=ThePlatonist.com}}</ref> Metaphysical justice has often been associated with concepts of [[destiny|fate]], [[reincarnation]] or [[Divine Providence]], i.e., with a life in accordance with a cosmic plan. The equivalence of justice and fairness has been historically and culturally established.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Daston |first=Lorraine |author-link=Lorraine Daston |year=2008 |journal=Daedalus |pages=5β14 |title=Life, Chance and Life Chances |doi=10.1162/daed.2008.137.1.5 |volume=137 |s2cid=57563698 |doi-access=free}}</ref> ===Instrumental theories of justice=== [[File:Justicia Ottawa.jpg|thumb|right|[[Walter Seymour Allward]]'s ''Justitia'' (Justice), outside [[Supreme Court of Canada]], [[Ottawa]], Ontario, Canada]] Instrumental theories of justice look at the consequences of [[punishment]] for wrongdoing, looking at questions such as:{{cn|date=February 2025}} # ''why'' punish? # ''who'' should be punished? # ''what'' punishment should they receive?{{cn|date=February 2025}} ===Utilitarian justice=== {{Main|Utilitarianism}} According to the utilitarian, justice is the maximization of the total or average welfare across all relevant individuals. Utilitarianism fights crime in three ways:<ref>{{Cite web |title=Punishment {{!}} Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |url=https://iep.utm.edu/punishme/ |access-date=5 October 2023 |language=en-US}}</ref> # ''[[Deterrence (legal)|Deterrence]]''. The credible [[coercion|threat]] of punishment might lead people to make different choices; well-designed threats might lead people to make choices that maximize welfare. This matches some strong [[intuition]]s about just punishment: that it should generally be proportional to the crime. Successful deterrence would reduce [[crime statistics]].<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1177/002242787401100204 |last1=Bailey |first1=William C. |last2=Martin |first2=J. David |last3=Gray |first3=Louis N. |title=Crime and deterrence: A correlation analysis |journal=[[Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency]] |volume=11 |number=2 |year=1974 |pages=124β143}}</ref> # ''[[Rehabilitation (penology)|Rehabilitation]]''. Punishment might make "bad people" into "better" ones. For the utilitarian, all that "bad person" can mean is "person who's likely to cause unwanted things (like suffering)". So, utilitarianism could recommend punishment that changes someone such that they are less likely to cause bad things. Successful rehabilitation would reduce [[recidivism]].<ref>{{cite book |last=Monahan |first=John |chapter=Preface: Recidivism Risk Assessment in the 21st Century |title=Handbook of Recidivism Risk/Needs Assessment Tools |date=2017}}</ref> # ''[[Incapacitation (penology)|Security/Incapacitation]]''. Perhaps there are people who are irredeemable causers of bad things. If so, [[Prison|imprisoning]] them might maximize welfare by limiting their opportunities to cause harm and therefore the benefit lies within protecting society. So, the reason for punishment is the maximization of welfare, and punishment should be of whomever, and of whatever form and severity, are needed to meet that goal. This may sometimes justify punishing the innocent, or inflicting disproportionately severe punishments, when that will have the best consequences overall (perhaps executing a few suspected [[Shoplifting|shoplifters]] live on television would be an effective deterrent to shoplifting, for instance). It also suggests that punishment might turn out ''never'' to be right, depending on the facts about what actual consequences it has.<ref>{{cite book |first=C. L. |last=Ten |chapter=Crime and Punishment |editor-first=Peter |editor-last=Singer |editor-link=Peter Singer |title=A Companion to Ethics |location=Oxford |publisher=[[Wiley-Blackwell|Blackwell Publishing]] |date=1993 |pages=366β372}}</ref> ===Retributive and Restorative justice=== {{Main|Retributive justice|Restorative justice}} Retributive justice argues that consequentialism is wrong, as it argues that all guilty individuals deserve appropriate punishment, based on the conviction that punishment should be proportional to the crime and for all the guilty.<ref>{{cite web |title=Punishment |url=https://www.csus.edu/indiv/g/gaskilld/ethics/punishment.htm |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210413204529/https://www.csus.edu/indiv/g/gaskilld/ethics/punishment.htm |archive-date=13 April 2021 |access-date=12 August 2020 |website=[[California State University]]}}</ref> However, it is sometimes said that retributivism is merely [[revenge]] in disguise.<ref>{{cite book |last=Honderich |first=Ted |title=Punishment: The supposed justifications |date=1969 |publisher=[[Hutchinson & Co.]] |location=London |chapter=1}}</ref> However, there are differences between retribution and revenge: the former is impartial and has a scale of appropriateness, whereas the latter is personal and potentially unlimited in scale.<ref>{{cite web |date=9 October 2015 |title=Retribution vs Revenge - What's the difference? |url=https://wikidiff.com/retribution/revenge}}</ref> Restorative justice attempts to repair the harm that was done to the victims.<ref>{{Cite web |last=Wilson |first=Jon |title=Victim-Centered Restorative Justice: An Essential Distinction |url=https://justalternatives.org/VCRJ.pdf}}</ref> It encourages active participation from victims and encourages offenders to take responsibility for their actions. Restorative justice fosters dialogue between victim and offender and shows the highest rates of victim satisfaction and offender accountability.<ref>Michael Braswell, and John Fuller, ''Corrections, Peacemaking and Restorative Justice: Transforming Individuals and Institutions'' ([[Routledge]], 2014).</ref> [[Meta-analysis|Meta-analyses]] of the effectivity of restorative justice show no improvement in [[recidivism]].<ref name="Schultheis">[[doi:10.1177/1748895823121522|Fulham, L., Blais, J., Rugge, T., & Schultheis, E. A. (2023). The effectiveness of restorative justice programs: A meta-analysis of recidivism and other relevant outcomes. Criminology & Criminal Justice, 0(0). 8]]</ref><ref name="Cochrane">{{cite journal |last1=Livingstone |first1=Nuala |last2=MacDonald |first2=Geraldine |last3=Carr |first3=Nicola |year=2013 |title=Restorative justice conferencing for reducing recidivism in young offenders (aged 7 to 21) |journal=Cochrane Database of Systematic Reviews |volume=2020 |issue=2 |pages=CD008898 |doi=10.1002/14651858.CD008898.pub2 |pmc=7388302 |pmid=23450592}}</ref> ====Welfare-maximization==== According to the utilitarian, justice requires the maximization of the total or average welfare across all relevant individuals.<ref>{{Cite web |title=The Project Gutenberg eBook of on Liberty, by John Stuart Mill. |url=https://www.gutenberg.org/files/34901/34901-h/34901-h.htm |access-date=3 May 2019 |via=Project Gutenberg}}</ref> This may require sacrifice of some for the good of others, so long as everyone's good is taken impartially into account. Utilitarianism, in general, says that the standard of justification for actions, institutions, or the whole world, is ''impartial welfare consequentialism'', and only indirectly, if at all, to do with [[Human rights|rights]], [[property]], [[need]], or any other non-utilitarian criterion. These other criteria might be indirectly important, to the extent that human welfare involves them. But even then, such demands as human rights would only be elements in the calculation of overall welfare, not uncrossable barriers to action.{{cn|date=February 2025}} ===Mixed theories=== Some modern philosophers have said that Utilitarian and Retributive theories are not mutually exclusive. For example, [[Andrew von Hirsch]], in his 1976 book ''Doing Justice'', suggested that we have a moral obligation to punish greater crimes more than lesser ones.<ref>{{cite book |first=Andrew |last=Von Hirsch |title=Doing Justice: The Choice of Punishments |location=Lebanon NH |publisher=[[Northeastern University Press]] |date=1976 |isbn=9780930350833}}</ref>{{pn|date=February 2025}} However, so long as we adhere to that constraint then utilitarian ideals would play a significant secondary role. ===Distributive justice=== {{Main|Distributive justice}} [[File:VD-04-3.jpg|thumb|{{Lang|la|Lex, justitia, pax}} ([[Latin]] for "Law, justice, peace") on the pediment of the [[Federal Supreme Court of Switzerland|Supreme Court of Switzerland]]]] Theories of distributive justice need to answer three questions:{{cn|date=February 2025}} # ''What goods'' are to be distributed? Is it to be wealth, [[Political power|power]], [[respect]], opportunities or some combination of these things? # ''Between what entities'' are they to be distributed? Humans (dead, living, future), [[Sentience|sentient]] beings, the members of a single society, nations? # What is the ''proper'' distribution? Equal, [[Meritocracy|meritocratic]], according to [[social status]], according to [[need]], based on property rights and non-aggression? Distributive justice theorists generally do not answer questions of ''who has the right'' to enforce a particular favored distribution, while property rights theorists say that there is no "favored distribution". Rather, distribution should be based simply on whatever distribution results from lawful interactions or transactions (that is, transactions which are not illicit).{{cn|date=February 2025}} ====Fairness==== {{More citations needed|date=February 2018}} [[File:Justice statue.jpg|thumb|J. L. Urban, statue of [[Lady Justice]] at court building in [[Olomouc]], Czech Republic]] {{Main|Right to a fair trial|}} In his ''[[A Theory of Justice]]'', [[John Rawls]] used a [[social contract]] argument to show that justice, and especially distributive justice, is a form of fairness: an impartial distribution of goods.{{cn|date=February 2025}} Rawls asks us to imagine ourselves behind a [[veil of ignorance]] that denies us all knowledge of our personalities, social statuses, moral characters, wealth, talents and life plans, and then asks what theory of justice we would choose to govern our society when the veil is lifted, if we wanted to do the best that we could for ourselves.{{cn|date=February 2025}} We do not know who in particular we are, and therefore can not bias the decision in our own favor. So, the decision-in-ignorance models fairness, because it excludes selfish [[bias]].{{cn|date=February 2025}} Rawls said that each of us would reject the [[utilitarianism|utilitarian]] theory of justice that we should maximize welfare (see above) because of the risk that we might turn out to be someone whose own good is sacrificed for greater benefits for others. Instead, we would endorse Rawls's ''two principles of justice'': * Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive total system of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar system of liberty for all. * Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both ** to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged, consistent with the just savings principle, and ** attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity.{{sfn|Rawls|1999|p=266}} This imagined choice justifies these principles as the principles of justice for us, because we would agree to them in a fair decision procedure. Rawls's theory distinguishes two kinds of goods β [[Freedom (political)|the good of liberty rights]] and social and economic goods, i.e. wealth, income, and power β and applies different distributions to them β equality between citizens for liberty rights and equality unless inequality improves the position of the worst off for social and economic goods.{{cn|date=February 2025}} In one sense, theories of distributive justice may assert that everyone should get what they deserve. Theories vary on the meaning of what is "deserved". The main distinction is between theories that say the basis of just deserts ought to be held equally by everyone, and therefore derive egalitarian accounts of distributive justice β and theories that say the basis of just deserts is unequally distributed on the basis of, for instance, hard work, and therefore derive accounts of distributive justice by which some should have more than others.{{cn|date=February 2025}} Studies at [[University of California, Los Angeles|UCLA]] in 2008 have indicated that reactions to fairness are "wired" into the brain and that, "Fairness is activating the same part of the brain that responds to food in rats... This is consistent with the notion that being treated fairly satisfies a basic need".<ref>{{cite news |url=http://newsroom.ucla.edu/portal/ucla/brain-reacts-to-fairness-as-it-49042.aspx?link_page_rss=49042 |title=Brain reacts to fairness as it does to money and chocolate, study shows |work=UCLA Newsroom |publisher=[[UCLA]] |date=21 April 2008 |access-date=15 January 2015 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20100226000010/http://newsroom.ucla.edu/portal/ucla/brain-reacts-to-fairness-as-it-49042.aspx?link_page_rss=49042 |archive-date=26 February 2010 |url-status=dead}}</ref> Research conducted in 2003 at [[Emory University]] involving capuchin monkeys demonstrated that other cooperative animals also possess such a sense and that "[[inequity aversion]] may [[inequity aversion in animals|not be]] uniquely human".<ref>Nature 425, 297β299 (18 September 2003)</ref>{{full citation needed|date=February 2025}} ====Property rights==== {{further|Libertarianism|Entitlement theory|Constitutional economics}} {{Unreferenced section|date=February 2018}} In ''[[Anarchy, State, and Utopia]]'', [[Robert Nozick]] said that distributive justice is not a matter of the whole distribution matching an ideal ''pattern'', but of each [[Entitlement theory|individual entitlement]] having the right kind of ''history''.{{cn|date=February 2025}} It is just that a person has some good (especially, some [[Property rights|property right]]) if and only if they came to have it by a history made up entirely of events of two kinds:{{cn|date=February 2025}} * Just ''acquisition'', especially by working on unowned things; and * Just ''transfer'', that is free gift, sale or other agreement, but not theft (i.e. by force or fraud). If the chain of events leading up to the person having something meets this criterion, they are entitled to it: that they possess it is just, and what anyone else does or does not have or need is irrelevant.{{cn|date=February 2025}} On the basis of this theory of distributive justice, Nozick said that all attempts to redistribute goods according to an ideal pattern, without the consent of their owners, are theft. In particular, [[redistribution (economics)|redistributive taxation]] is theft.{{cn|date=February 2025}} Some property rights theorists (such as Nozick) also take a consequentialist view of distributive justice and say that property rights based justice also has the effect of maximizing the overall wealth of an economic system. They explain that voluntary (non-coerced) transactions always have a property called [[Pareto efficiency]]. The result is that the world is better off in an absolute sense and no one is worse off.{{cn|date=February 2025}} They say that respecting property rights maximizes the number of Pareto efficient transactions in the world and minimized the number of non-Pareto efficient transactions in the world (i.e. transactions where someone is made worse off). The result is that the world will have generated the greatest total benefit from the limited, scarce resources available in the world. Further, this will have been accomplished without taking anything away from anyone unlawfully.{{cn|date=February 2025}} ====Meritocracy==== According to ''[[Meritocracy|meritocratic]]'' theories, goods, especially wealth and [[social status]], should be distributed to match individual ''merit'', which is usually understood as some combination of talent and hard work. According to ''[[need]]s''-based theories, goods, especially such basic goods as food, shelter, and medical care, should be distributed to meet individuals' [[basic needs]] for them.{{cn|date=February 2025}} According to ''contribution''-based theories, goods should be distributed to match an individual's contribution to the overall social good.{{cn|date=February 2025}}
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Justice
(section)
Add topic