Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Homomorphism
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
===Epimorphism=== In [[algebra]], '''epimorphisms''' are often defined as [[surjective]] homomorphisms.<ref name="Birkhoff.1967"/>{{rp|134}}<ref name="Burris.Sankappanavar.2012" />{{rp|43}} On the other hand, in [[category theory]], [[epimorphism]]s are defined as '''right cancelable''' [[morphism]]s.<ref name=workmath/> This means that a (homo)morphism <math>f: A \to B</math> is an epimorphism if, for any pair <math>g</math>, <math>h</math> of morphisms from <math>B</math> to any other object <math>C</math>, the equality <math>g \circ f = h \circ f</math> implies <math>g = h</math>. A surjective homomorphism is always right cancelable, but the converse is not always true for algebraic structures. However, the two definitions of ''epimorphism'' are equivalent for [[set (mathematics)|sets]], [[vector space]]s, [[abelian group]]s, [[module (mathematics)|modules]] (see below for a proof), and [[group (mathematics)|groups]].<ref>{{cite journal |last=Linderholm |first=C. E. |year=1970 |title=A group epimorphism is surjective |journal=The American Mathematical Monthly |volume=77 |issue=2 |pages=176–177|doi=10.1080/00029890.1970.11992448 }}</ref> The importance of these structures in all mathematics, especially in [[linear algebra]] and [[homological algebra]], may explain the coexistence of two non-equivalent definitions. Algebraic structures for which there exist non-surjective epimorphisms include [[semigroup]]s and [[ring (mathematics)|rings]]. The most basic example is the inclusion of [[integer]]s into [[rational number]]s, which is a homomorphism of rings and of multiplicative semigroups. For both structures it is a monomorphism and a non-surjective epimorphism, but not an isomorphism.<ref name=workmath/><ref>{{cite book | page=363 | title=Hopf Algebra: An Introduction | zbl=0962.16026 | series=Pure and Applied Mathematics | volume=235 | location=New York City | publisher=Marcel Dekker | first1=Sorin | last1=Dăscălescu | first2=Constantin | last2=Năstăsescu | first3=Șerban | last3=Raianu | year=2001 | isbn=0824704819 }}</ref> A wide generalization of this example is the [[localization of a ring]] by a multiplicative set. Every localization is a ring epimorphism, which is not, in general, surjective. As localizations are fundamental in [[commutative algebra]] and [[algebraic geometry]], this may explain why in these areas, the definition of epimorphisms as right cancelable homomorphisms is generally preferred. A '''[[split epimorphism]]''' is a homomorphism that has a [[inverse function#Left and right inverses|right inverse]] and thus it is itself a left inverse of that other homomorphism. That is, a homomorphism <math>f\colon A \to B</math> is a split epimorphism if there exists a homomorphism <math>g\colon B \to A</math> such that <math>f\circ g = \operatorname{Id}_B.</math> A split epimorphism is always an epimorphism, for both meanings of ''epimorphism''. For sets and vector spaces, every epimorphism is a split epimorphism, but this property does not hold for most common algebraic structures. In summary, one has <math display="block">\text {split epimorphism} \implies \text{epimorphism (surjective)}\implies \text {epimorphism (right cancelable)};</math> the last implication is an equivalence for sets, vector spaces, modules, abelian groups, and groups; the first implication is an equivalence for sets and vector spaces. {{collapse top|Equivalence of the two definitions of epimorphism}} Let <math>f\colon A \to B</math> be a homomorphism. We want to prove that if it is not surjective, it is not right cancelable. In the case of sets, let <math>b</math> be an element of <math>B</math> that not belongs to <math>f(A)</math>, and define <math>g, h\colon B \to B</math> such that <math>g</math> is the [[identity function]], and that <math>h(x) = x</math> for every <math>x \in B,</math> except that <math>h(b)</math> is any other element of <math>B</math>. Clearly <math>f</math> is not right cancelable, as <math>g \neq h</math> and <math>g \circ f = h \circ f.</math> In the case of vector spaces, abelian groups and modules, the proof relies on the existence of [[cokernel]]s and on the fact that the [[zero map]]s are homomorphisms: let <math>C</math> be the cokernel of <math>f</math>, and <math>g\colon B \to C</math> be the canonical map, such that <math>g(f(A)) = 0</math>. Let <math>h\colon B\to C</math> be the zero map. If <math>f</math> is not surjective, <math>C \neq 0</math>, and thus <math>g \neq h</math> (one is a zero map, while the other is not). Thus <math>f</math> is not cancelable, as <math>g \circ f = h \circ f</math> (both are the zero map from <math>A</math> to <math>C</math>). {{cob}}
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Homomorphism
(section)
Add topic