Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Hylomorphism
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Legacy== ===Universal hylomorphism=== The [[neoplatonism|Neoplatonic]] philosopher [[Solomon ibn Gabirol|Avicebron (Solomon ibn Gabirol)]] proposed a Neoplatonic version of this Aristotelian concept, according to which all things, including soul and intellect, are composed of matter and form.<ref name=stanford>{{cite encyclopedia | last1 = Pessin | first1 = Sarah | editor-last = Zalta | editor-first = Edward N. | title = Solomon Ibn Gabirol [Avicebron] | encyclopedia = The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy | edition = Summer 2014 | date = April 18, 2014 | url = http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ibn-gabirol/ | access-date = October 13, 2015}}</ref> {{Quote|With respect to Averroes’s view, what, if only I knew, could necessitate that we not say this very thing in the case of bodies that come to be and pass away, namely, that the matter they contain is their corporeality, and their form the form that is specific to each one and serves each one as the perfection of its corporeality? Corporeality, which he calls “corporeal form,” would then function as matter with respect to its specific form. If so, the matter, even without its specific form, would be in need of a place and would exist in actuality. Behold, my witness is in heaven, since the celestial body, which is a body without matter, is one that exists in actuality. In this way, many difficult and perplexing questions regarding hylic nature as it is generally understood will be resolved. It is open, therefore, to an objector to say that it is not a specific form through which a body exists, but that the corporeal form, which is the substratum in actuality, is that which sustains the specific form|[[Hasdai Crescas]]}} Hasdai Crescas imagines that celestial-body is like Hylé but as matter in actuality, sure over the opposition about this, i.e. in potential existence. Matter and form is always presents in all but celestial-bodies are without form because of their nature; so Hasdai Crescas finds the solution also about this paradox.<ref>Hasdai Crescas teaches that the proof of Existence of God and the Creation of World by [[Maimonides]] could be explained with parallel-exegesis about the elements of the same proof: Hasdai Crescas and Maimonides teach with words of philosophy but logical-reasons can explain only first view. The second view, that is esoteric-exegesis (the [[Kabbalah]]) could be understood with [[Torah]]: ''This is the totality of what we saw fit to say in our concise manner by way of response to the Rabbi’s proofs. It is evident that the number of responses from the first perspective parallels the number of propositions that we mentioned that the Rabbi used. These are in addition to the responses from the second perspective in which we granted the truth of those propositions. What this condition of confusion teaches is that that which provides the truth with respect to these theses has not to this day been fully grasped by recourse to the philosophers. Indeed, the only thing that illuminates all of these deep difficulties is the Torah.''</ref> ===Medieval modifications=== Thomas Aquinas emphasized the act/potency understanding of form/matter whereby form activates the potency of matter and existence activates souls. The angels are accordingly composites of esse (potentiality) and [[Actus essendi|existence]] (actuality) that activates immaterial souls, while God alone is per se existence, pure act without any potencies. [[Medieval]] [[theology|theologians]], newly exposed to Aristotle's philosophy, applied hylomorphism to Christian doctrines such as the [[transubstantiation]] of the Eucharist's bread and wine into the body and blood of [[Jesus]]. Theologians such as [[Duns Scotus]] and [[Thomas Aquinas]] developed Christian applications of hylomorphism. Aristotle's texts on the agent intellect have given rise to diverse interpretations. Some following [[Averroes]] (Ibn Rushd 1126–1198) argue that Aristotle equated the active intellect with a divine being who infuses concepts into the passive intellect to aid human understanding. Others following Aquinas (1225–74) argue that the Neoplatonic interpretation is a mistake: the active intellect is actually part of the human soul. ====Substantial form, accidental form, and prime matter==== {{See also|Substantial form}} Medieval philosophers who used Aristotelian concepts frequently distinguished between [[substantial form]]s and accidental forms. A substance necessarily possesses at least one substantial form. It may also possess a variety of accidental forms. For Aristotle, a "substance" (''ousia'') is an individual thing—for example, an individual man or an individual horse.<ref>''Categories'' 2a12-14</ref> Within every physical substance, the substantial form determines what kind of thing the physical substance is by actualizing prime matter as individualized by the causes of that thing's coming to be. For instance, the chick comes to be when the substantial form of chickens actualizes the hen's egg and that actualization is possible insofar as that egg is in potency to being actualized both as a chicken due to the receptivity of its prime matter to the substantial form of chickens and into a chick with certain colored feathers due to the individualization of the egg given by its parents. So while the individualized matter determines individualized properties, the substantial form determines essential properties. The substantial form of substance S consists of S's essence and its essential properties (the properties that S needs in order to be the kind of substance that S is<ref>Cross 34</ref><ref name="Kenny 24">Kenny 24</ref>). Substantial change destroys the ability of a substantial form to actualize individualized prime matter without affecting prime matter's ability to be actualized by a new substantial form.<ref>Leftow 136-37</ref> When the wolf eats the chick, the chick's rearranged matter becomes part of the wolf and animated by the wolf's substantial form. In contrast, S's accidental forms are S's non-essential properties,<ref>Cross 94</ref> properties that S can lose or gain without changing into a different kind of substance.<ref name="Kenny 24"/> The chick can lose its feathers due to parasites without ceasing to be an individual chicken. ====Plurality vs. unity of substantial form==== Many medieval theologians and philosophers followed Aristotle in seeing a living being's soul as that being's form—specifically, its substantial form. However, they disagreed about whether X's soul is X's ''only'' substantial form. Some medieval thinkers argued that X's soul is X's only substantial form animating the entire body of X.<ref>Kenny 26</ref> In contrast, other medieval thinkers argued that a living being contains at least two substantial forms—(1) the shape and structure of its body, and (2) its soul, which makes its body alive.<ref>Cross 70</ref> ====Thomistic hylomorphism<!--Linked from 'Thomas Aquinas'-->==== {{Thomism}} [[Thomas Aquinas]] claimed that X's soul was X's only [[substantial form]], although X also had numerous accidental forms that accounted for X's nonessential features.<ref name="ReferenceB">Stump, "Resurrection, Reassembly, and Reconstitution: Aquinas on the Soul" 161.</ref><ref>Stump, "Resurrection, Reassembly, and Reconstitution: Aquinas on the Soul" 165</ref> Aquinas defined a substantial form as that which makes X's matter constitute X, which in the case of a human being is also able to transcend the limitations of matter and establish both the [[reason|rational capacity]]<ref>Leftow, "Soul, Mind, and Brain" 397.</ref> and natural immortality of human beings. Nevertheless, Aquinas did not claim that human persons were their disembodied souls because the human soul is essentially a substantial form activating matter into the body. He held that a proper human being is a composite of the rational soul and matter (both prime matter and individualized matter).<ref>Eberl 340</ref><ref>Eberl 341</ref> So a soul separated from its body does not become an angel but retains its orientation to animate matter, while a corpse from which the soul has departed is not actually or potentially a human being.<ref name="ReferenceB"/> [[Eleonore Stump]] describes Aquinas' theory of the soul in terms of "configuration". The body is matter that is "configured", i.e. structured, while the soul is a "configured configurer". In other words, the soul is itself a configured thing, but it also configures the body.<ref>Stump, "Non-Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism without Reductionism" 514.</ref> A dead body is merely matter that was once configured by the soul. It does not possess the configuring capacity of a human being. Aquinas believed that rational capacity was a property of the soul alone, not of any bodily organ.<ref>Stump,"Non-Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism without Reductionism" 512.</ref> However, he did believe that the brain had some basic cognitive function.<ref>Stump, "Non-Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism without Reductionism" 512.</ref> Aquinas’ attribution of rational capacity to the immaterial soul allowed him to claim that disembodied souls could retain their rational capacity as his identification of the soul's individual act of existence allowed him to claim that personal immortality is natural for human beings. Aquinas was also adamant that disembodied souls were in an unnatural state<ref>Stump, "Non-Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism without Reductionism" 519.</ref> and that the perfection of heaven includes God miraculously enabling the soul to function once again as a substantial form by reanimating matter into a living body as promised by the doctrine of the resurrection of the dead. ===Modern physics=== The idea of hylomorphism can be said to have been reintroduced to the world when [[Werner Heisenberg]] invented his duplex world of [[quantum mechanics]]. In his 1958 text ''Physics and Philosophy'', Heisenberg states: {{blockquote|In the experiments about atomic events we have to do with things and facts, with phenomena that are just as real as any phenomena in daily life. But atoms and the elementary particles themselves are not as real; they form a world of potentialities or possibilities rather than one of things or facts ... The probability wave ... mean[s] tendency for something. It's a quantitative version of the old concept of potentia from Aristotle's philosophy. It introduces something standing in the middle between the idea of an event and the actual event, a strange kind of physical reality just in the middle between possibility and reality.<ref>{{cite book |last=Heisenberg |first=Werner |date=1959 |title=Physics and Philosophy |url=https://ia800506.us.archive.org/BookReader/BookReaderImages.php?zip=/4/items/ost-physics-heisenberg-physicsphilosophy/Heisenberg-PhysicsPhilosophy_jp2.zip&file=Heisenberg-PhysicsPhilosophy_jp2/Heisenberg-PhysicsPhilosophy_0080.jp2&id=ost-physics-heisenberg-physicsphilosophy&scale=4&rotate=0 |location=London |publisher=George Allen & Unwin Ltd |page=160 |isbn=004530016X}}</ref>}} A hylomorphic interpretation of [[Bohmian mechanics]] has been suggested, in which the cosmos is a single substance that is composed of both material particles and a substantial form.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Simpson |first1=William M. R. |date=2021-01-15 |title=Cosmic hylomorphism: A powerist ontology of quantum mechanics |journal=European Journal for Philosophy of Science |volume=11 |issue=1 |pages=29 ff |doi=10.1007/s13194-020-00342-5|pmid=33520035 |pmc=7831748 |doi-access=free }}</ref> There is also a hylomorphic interpretation of the [[collapse of the wave function]].<ref>{{cite book |last=Simpson |first=William M. R. |date=2021-10-11 |editor1-last=Simpson |editor1-first=William M. R. |editor2-last=Koons |editor2-first=Robert C. |editor3-last=Orr |editor3-first=James |title=Neo-Aristotelian Metaphysics and the Theology of Nature |url=https://www.taylorfrancis.com/books/edit/10.4324/9781003125860/ |location=New York |publisher=Routledge |via=Taylor & Francis Group |pages=21–65 |chapter=From Quantum Physics to Classical Metaphysics |isbn=9781003125860 |doi=10.4324/9781003125860|s2cid=244179976 }}</ref>
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Hylomorphism
(section)
Add topic