Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Cardinality
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
=== Ancient History === [[File:AristotlesWheelLabeledDiagram.svg|thumb|252x252px|Diagram of Aristotle's wheel as described in ''Mechanica''.]] From the 6th century BCE, the writings of Greek philosophers show hints of infinite cardinality. While they considered generally infinity as an endless series of actions, such as adding 1 to a number repeatedly, they considered rarely infinite sets ([[actual infinity]]), and, if they did, they considered infinity as a unique cardinality.<ref name="Allen2">{{Cite web |last=Allen |first=Donald |date=2003 |title=The History of Infinity |url=https://www.math.tamu.edu/~dallen/masters/infinity/infinity.pdf |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200801202539/https://www.math.tamu.edu/~dallen/masters/infinity/infinity.pdf |archive-date=August 1, 2020 |access-date=Nov 15, 2019 |website=Texas A&M Mathematics}}</ref> The ancient Greek notion of infinity also considered the division of things into parts repeated without limit. One of the earliest explicit uses of a one-to-one correspondence is recorded in [[Aristotle]]'s [[Mechanics (Aristotle)|''Mechanics'']] ({{Circa|350 BC}}), known as [[Aristotle's wheel paradox]]. The paradox can be briefly described as follows: A wheel is depicted as two [[concentric circles]]. The larger, outer circle is tangent to a horizontal line (e.g. a road that it rolls on), while the smaller, inner circle is rigidly affixed to the larger. Assuming the larger circle rolls along the line without slipping (or skidding) for one full revolution, the distances moved by both circles are the same: the [[circumference]] of the larger circle. Further, the lines traced by the bottom-most point of each is the same length.<ref name=":0">{{Cite journal |last=Drabkin |first=Israel E. |date=1950 |title=Aristotle's Wheel: Notes on the History of a Paradox |journal=Osiris |volume=9 |pages=162β198 |doi=10.1086/368528 |jstor=301848 |s2cid=144387607}}</ref> Since the smaller wheel does not skip any points, and no point on the smaller wheel is used more than once, there is a one-to-one correspondence between the two circles.
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Cardinality
(section)
Add topic