Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Antonio Gramsci
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Philosophical work== [[File:Antonio Gramsci - Molti quaderni colorati del carcere.jpg|thumb|Gramsci's many prison notebooks]] Gramsci was one of the most influential Marxist thinkers of the 20th century, and a particularly key thinker in the development of [[Western Marxism]]. He wrote more than 30 notebooks and 3,000 pages of history and analysis during his imprisonment. These writings, known as the ''[[Prison Notebooks]]'', contain Gramsci's tracing of [[Italian history]] and [[nationalism]], as well as some ideas in [[Marxist theory]], [[critical theory]], and educational theory associated with his name, such as: * [[Cultural hegemony]] as a means of maintaining and legitimising the [[capitalist state]] * The need for [[Popular education|popular workers' education]] to encourage the development of intellectuals from the working class * An analysis of the modern capitalist state that distinguishes between [[political society]], which dominates directly and coercively, and [[civil society]], where leadership is constituted through consent * Absolute [[historicism]] * A critique of [[economic determinism]] that opposes [[fatalistic]] interpretations of Marxism * A critique of [[materialism|philosophical materialism]] ===Hegemony=== {{Marxism}} {{Communism in Italy|expanded=People}} {{further|Cultural hegemony}} [[Hegemony]] was a term previously used by Marxists such as [[Vladimir Lenin]] to denote the political leadership of the working class in a democratic revolution.<ref name=NLR>{{cite journal | last = Anderson | first = Perry | author-link = Perry Anderson | title = The Antinomies of Antonio Gramsci | journal = [[New Left Review]] | volume = I | issue = 100 | pages = 5–78 | publisher = New Left Review | date = November–December 1976 | url = http://newleftreview.org/I/100/perry-anderson-the-antinomies-of-antonio-gramsci | archive-date = 28 December 2015 | access-date = 7 January 2016 | archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20151228162258/http://newleftreview.org/I/100/perry-anderson-the-antinomies-of-antonio-gramsci | url-status = live }}</ref>{{rp|15–17}} Gramsci greatly expanded this concept, developing an acute analysis of how the ruling capitalist class—the [[bourgeoisie]]—establishes and maintains its control.<ref name=NLR />{{rp|20}} [[Classical Marxism]] had predicted that socialist revolution was inevitable in capitalist societies. By the early 20th century, no such revolution had occurred in the most advanced nations, and those [[revolutions of 1917–1923]], such as in Germany or the [[Biennio Rosso]] in Italy, had failed. As capitalism seemed more entrenched than ever, Gramsci suggested that it maintained control not just through violence and political and economic coercion but also through [[ideology]]. The [[bourgeoisie]] developed a hegemonic culture, which propagated its own values and norms so that they became the [[common sense]] values of all. People in the working class and other classes identified their own good with the good of the bourgeoisie and helped to maintain the ''status quo'' rather than revolting. To counter the notion that bourgeois values represented natural or normal values for society, the working class needed to develop a culture of its own. While Lenin held that culture was ancillary to political objectives, Gramsci saw it as fundamental to the attainment of power that cultural hegemony be achieved first. In Gramsci's view, a class cannot dominate in modern conditions by merely advancing its own narrow economic interests, and neither can it dominate purely through force and coercion.{{sfn|Sassoon|1991c|p=230}} Rather, it must exert intellectual and moral leadership, and make alliances and compromises with a variety of forces.{{sfn|Sassoon|1991c|p=230}} Gramsci calls this union of social forces a ''historic bloc'', taking a term from [[Georges Sorel]]. This bloc forms the basis of consent to a certain social order, which produces and re-produces the hegemony of the dominant class through a nexus of institutions, [[social relation]]s, and ideas.{{sfn|Sassoon|1991c|p=230}} In this way, Gramsci's theory emphasized the importance of the political and ideological [[Base and superstructure|superstructure]] in both maintaining and fracturing relations of the economic base. Gramsci stated that bourgeois cultural values were tied to [[folklore]], popular culture and religion, and therefore much of his analysis of hegemonic culture is aimed at these. He was also impressed by the influence that the [[Catholic Church]] had and the care it had taken to prevent an excessive gap from developing between the religion of the learned and that of the less educated. Gramsci saw Marxism as a marriage of the purely intellectual critique of religion found in [[Renaissance humanism]] and the elements of the [[Reformation]] that had appealed to the masses. For Gramsci, Marxism could supersede religion only if it met people's spiritual needs, and to do so people would have to think of it as an expression of their own experience. ===Intellectuals and education=== Gramsci gave much thought to the role of intellectuals in society.{{sfn|Kiernan|1991|p=259}} He stated that all men are intellectuals, in that all have intellectual and rational faculties, but not all men have the social function of intellectuals.{{sfn|Gramsci|1971|p=9}} He saw modern intellectuals not as talkers but as practical-minded directors and organisers who produced hegemony through ideological apparatuses such as education and the media. Furthermore, he distinguished between a traditional [[intelligentsia]], which sees itself (in his view, wrongly) as a class apart from society, and the thinking groups that every class produces from its own ranks organically.{{sfn|Kiernan|1991|p=259}} Such organic intellectuals do not simply describe social life in accordance with scientific rules but instead articulate, through the language of culture, the feelings and experiences which the masses could not express for themselves. To Gramsci, it was the duty of organic intellectuals to speak to the obscured precepts of folk wisdom, or common sense (''senso comune''), of their respective political spheres. These intellectuals would represent excluded social groups of a society, or what Gramsci referred to as the [[Subaltern (postcolonialism)|subaltern]].<ref>{{cite book|last1=Crehan|first1=Kate|title=Gramsci's Common Sense: Inequality and Its Narratives|date=2016|publisher=Duke University Press|isbn=978-0-8223-6219-7|url-access=registration|url=https://archive.org/details/gramsciscommonse00creh_2}}</ref> In line with Gramsci's theories of cultural hegemony, he argued that capitalist power needed to be challenged by building a [[counter-hegemony]]. By this, he meant that, as part of the war of position, the organic intellectuals and others within the working-class, need to develop alternative values and an alternative ideology in contrast to bourgeois ideology. He argued that the reason this had not needed to happen in Russia was because the Russian ruling class did not have genuine cultural hegemony. So the [[Bolsheviks]] were able to carry out a war of manoeuvre (the [[Russian Revolution of 1917]]) relatively easily because ruling-class hegemony had never been fully achieved. He believed that a final war of manoeuvre was only possible, in the developed and advanced capitalist societies, when the war of position had been won by the organic intellectuals and the working class building a counter-hegemony. The need to create a [[working-class culture]] and a counter-hegemony relates to Gramsci's call for a kind of education that could develop working-class intellectuals, whose task was {{em|not}} to introduce Marxist ideology into the consciousness of the proletariat as a set of foreign notions but to renovate the existing intellectual activity of the masses and make it natively critical of the status quo. His ideas about an education system for this purpose correspond with the notion of [[critical pedagogy]] and [[popular education]] as theorized and practised in later decades by [[Paulo Freire]] in Brazil, and have much in common with the thought of [[Frantz Fanon]]. For this reason, partisans of adult and popular education consider Gramsci's writings and ideas important to this day.<ref>{{cite journal|last=Mayo|first=Peter|date=June 2008|title=Antonio Gramsci and his Relevance for the Education of Adults|journal=Educational Philosophy & Theory|volume=40|issue=3|pages=418–435|doi=10.1111/j.1469-5812.2007.00357.x|s2cid=143570823|url=https://www.um.edu.mt/library/oar/bitstream/123456789/44580/1/Antonio_Gramsci_and_his_relevance_to_the_education_of_adults.pdf|archive-date=24 September 2019|access-date=24 September 2019|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190924094014/https://www.um.edu.mt/library/oar/bitstream/123456789/44580/1/Antonio_Gramsci_and_his_relevance_to_the_education_of_adults.pdf|url-status=live}}</ref> ===State and civil society=== Gramsci's theory of hegemony is tied to his conception of the capitalist state. Gramsci does not understand the state in the narrow sense of the government. Instead, he divides it between political society (the police, the army, legal system, etc.)—the arena of political institutions and legal constitutional control—and [[civil society]] (the family, the education system, trade unions, etc.)—commonly seen as the private or non-state sphere, which mediates between the state and the economy.{{sfn|Sassoon|1991b|p=83}} He stresses that the division is purely conceptual and that the two often overlap in reality.{{sfn|Gramsci|1971|p=160}} Gramsci posits that the capitalist state rules through force plus consent: political society is the realm of force and civil society is the realm of consent. He argues that under modern capitalism the bourgeoisie can maintain its economic control by allowing certain demands made by trade unions and mass political parties within civil society to be met by the political sphere. Thus, the bourgeoisie engages in [[passive revolution]] by going beyond its immediate economic interests and allowing the forms of its hegemony to change. Gramsci posits that movements such as [[reformism]] and fascism, as well as the [[scientific management]] and [[assembly line]] methods of [[Frederick Winslow Taylor]] and [[Henry Ford]] respectively, are examples of this. Drawing from [[Niccolò Machiavelli]], Gramsci argues that the modern [[The Prince|Prince]]—the revolutionary party—is the force that will allow the working class to develop organic intellectuals and an alternative hegemony within civil society. For Gramsci, the complex nature of modern civil society means that a war of position, carried out by revolutionaries through political agitation, the trade unions, advancement of [[proletarian culture]], and other ways to create an opposing civil society was necessary alongside a war of manoeuvre—a direct revolution—in order to have a successful revolution without danger of a counter-revolution or degeneration. Despite his claim that the lines between the two may be blurred, Gramsci rejects the state worship that results from equating political society with civil society, as was done by the [[Jacobin (politics)|Jacobins]] and fascists. He believes the proletariat's historical task is to create a regulated society, where political society is diminished and civil society is expanded. He defines the [[withering away of the state]] as the full development of civil society's ability to regulate itself.{{sfn|Sassoon|1991b|p=83}} ===Historicism=== Like the [[young Marx]], Gramsci was an emphatic proponent of [[historicism]].{{sfn|Gramsci|1971|pp=404–407}} In Gramsci's view, all meaning derives from the relation between human practical activity (or [[praxis (process)|praxis]]) and the objective historical and social processes of which it is a part. Ideas cannot be understood outside their social and historical context, apart from their function and origin. The concepts by which we organise our knowledge of the world do not derive primarily from our relation to [[object (philosophy)|objects]], but rather from the [[social relation]]s between the users of those concepts. As a result, there is no such thing as an unchanging [[human nature]] but only historically variable social relationships. Furthermore, philosophy and science do not reflect a reality independent of man. Rather, a theory can be said to be true when, in any given historical situation, it expresses the real developmental trend of that situation. For the majority of Marxists, truth was truth no matter when and where it was known, and scientific knowledge, which included Marxism, accumulated historically as the advance of truth in this everyday sense. In this view, Marxism (or the Marxist theory of history and economics) did not belong to the illusory realm of the superstructure because it is a science. In contrast, Gramsci believed Marxism was true in a socially pragmatic sense: by articulating the [[class consciousness]] of the [[proletariat]], Marxism expressed the truth of its times better than any other theory. This anti-[[scientistic]] and anti-[[positivist]] stance was indebted to the influence of [[Benedetto Croce]]. At the same time, it should be underlined that Gramsci's absolute historicism broke with Croce's tendency to secure a metaphysical synthesis of historical destiny. Although Gramsci repudiates the charge, his historical account of truth has been criticised as a form of [[relativism]].<ref name=Kolakowski2>{{cite book |date=1978 |title=Leszek Kolakowski – Main Currents of Marxism – Its Rise, Growth and, Dissolution – Volume III – The Breakdown |url=https://archive.org/details/maincurrentsofma00kola/page/228 |publisher=Oxford University Press |pages=[https://archive.org/details/maincurrentsofma00kola/page/228 228–231] |isbn=978-0-19-824570-4 }}</ref> ===Critique of economism=== In a pre-prison article titled "The Revolution against {{italics correction|''[[Das Kapital]]''}}", Gramsci wrote that the [[October Revolution]] in Russia had invalidated the idea that socialist revolution had to await the full development of capitalist forces of production.{{sfn|Sassoon|1991a|p=221}} This reflected his view that Marxism was not a [[determinist]] philosophy. The principle of the causal primacy of the forces of production was a misconception of Marxism. Both economic changes and cultural changes are expressions of a basic historical process, and it is difficult to say which sphere has primacy over the other. The belief from the earliest years of the [[workers' movement]] that it would inevitably triumph due to historical laws was a product of the historical circumstances of an oppressed class restricted mainly to defensive action. This [[fatalistic]] doctrine must be abandoned as a hindrance once the working class becomes able to take the initiative. Because Marxism is a philosophy of praxis, it cannot rely on unseen historical laws as the agents of social change. History is defined by human praxis and therefore includes human will. Nonetheless, willpower cannot achieve anything it likes in any given situation: when the consciousness of the working class reaches the stage of development necessary for action, it will encounter historical circumstances that cannot be arbitrarily altered. It is not predetermined by historical inevitability as to which of several possible developments will take place as a result. His critique of [[economic determinism]] extended to that practised by the syndicalists of the Italian trade unions. He believed that many trade unionists had settled for a reformist, gradualist approach in that they had refused to struggle on the political front in addition to the economic front. For Gramsci, much as the ruling class can look beyond its own immediate economic interests to reorganise the forms of its own hegemony, so must the working class present its own interests as congruous with the universal advancement of society. While Gramsci envisioned the trade unions as one organ of a counter-hegemonic force in a capitalist society, the trade union leaders simply saw these organizations as a means to improve conditions within the existing structure. Gramsci referred to the views of these trade unionists as vulgar economism, which he equated to covert reformism and [[liberalism]]. ===Critique of materialism=== By virtue of his belief that human history and collective praxis determine whether any philosophical question is meaningful or not, Gramsci's views run contrary to the metaphysical materialism and copy theory of perception advanced by [[Friedrich Engels]],<ref>Friedrich Engels: [http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1877/anti-duhring/index.htm ''Anti-Duehring''] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20050911162121/http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1877/anti-duhring/index.htm |date=11 September 2005 }}</ref><ref>Friedrich Engels: [http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1883/don/index.htm ''Dialectics of Nature''] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20100325174639/http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1883/don/index.htm |date=25 March 2010 }}</ref> and Lenin,<ref>Lenin: [http://www.marxists.org/archive/lenin/works/1908/mec/index.htm ''Materialism and Empirio-Criticism''] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20201203171158/https://www.marxists.org/archive/lenin/works/1908/mec/index.htm |date=3 December 2020 }}.</ref> although he does not explicitly state this. For Gramsci, Marxism does not deal with a reality that exists in and for itself, independent of humanity.{{sfn|Gramsci|1971|pp=440–448}} The concept of an [[Objectivity (philosophy)|objective]] universe outside of human history and human praxis was analogous to belief in God.{{sfn|Gramsci|1971|p=445}} Gramsci defined objectivity in terms of a universal [[intersubjectivity]] to be established in a future communist society.{{sfn|Gramsci|1971|p=445}} Natural history was thus only meaningful in relation to human history. In his view philosophical materialism resulted from a lack of critical thought,{{sfn|Gramsci|1971|pp=444–445}} and could not be said to oppose religious dogma and superstition.{{sfn|Gramsci|1971|p=420}} Despite this, Gramsci resigned himself to the existence of this arguably cruder form of Marxism. Marxism was a philosophy for the proletariat, a subaltern class, and thus could often only be expressed in the form of popular superstition and common sense.{{sfn|Gramsci|1971|pp=419–425}} Nonetheless, it was necessary to effectively challenge the ideologies of the educated classes and to do so Marxists must present their philosophy in a more sophisticated guise and attempt to genuinely understand their opponents' views.
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Antonio Gramsci
(section)
Add topic