Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Intermediate value theorem
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
=== Proof version A=== <!-- This section is linked from [[Continuity property]] --> The theorem may be proven as a consequence of the [[completeness (order theory)|completeness]] property of the real numbers as follows:<ref>Essentially follows {{cite book |title=Foundations of Analysis|first=Douglas A.|last=Clarke|publisher=Appleton-Century-Crofts | year=1971|page=284}}</ref> We shall prove the first case, <math>f(a) < u < f(b)</math>. The second case is similar. Let <math>S</math> be the set of all <math>x \in [a,b]</math> such that <math>f(x)<u</math>. Then <math>S</math> is non-empty since <math>a</math> is an element of <math>S</math>. Since <math>S</math> is non-empty and bounded above by <math>b</math>, by completeness, the [[supremum]] <math>c=\sup S</math> exists. That is, <math>c</math> is the smallest number that is greater than or equal to every member of <math>S</math>. Note that, due to the continuity of <math>f</math> at <math>a</math>, we can keep <math>f(x)</math> within any <math>\varepsilon>0</math> of <math>f(a)</math> by keeping <math>x</math> sufficiently close to <math>a</math>. Since <math>f(a)<u</math> is a strict inequality, consider the implication when <math>\varepsilon</math> is the distance between <math>u</math> and <math>f(a)</math>. No <math>x</math> sufficiently close to <math>a</math> can then make <math>f(x)</math> greater than or equal to <math>u</math>, which means there are values greater than <math>a</math> in <math>S</math>. A more detailed proof goes like this: Choose <math>\varepsilon=u-f(a)>0</math>. Then <math>\exists \delta>0</math> such that <math>\forall x \in [a,b]</math>, <math display="block">|x-a|<\delta \implies |f(x)-f(a)|<u-f(a) \implies f(x)<u.</math>Consider the interval <math>[a,\min(a+\delta,b))=I_1</math>. Notice that <math>I_1 \subseteq [a,b]</math> and every <math>x \in I_1</math> satisfies the condition <math>|x-a|<\delta</math>. Therefore for every <math>x \in I_1</math> we have <math>f(x)<u</math>. Hence <math>c</math> cannot be <math>a</math>. Likewise, due to the continuity of <math>f</math> at <math>b</math>, we can keep <math>f(x)</math> within any <math>\varepsilon > 0</math> of <math>f(b)</math> by keeping <math>x</math> sufficiently close to <math>b</math>. Since <math>u<f(b)</math> is a strict inequality, consider the similar implication when <math>\varepsilon</math> is the distance between <math>u</math> and <math>f(b)</math>. Every <math>x</math> sufficiently close to <math>b</math> must then make <math>f(x)</math> greater than <math>u</math>, which means there are values smaller than <math>b</math> that are upper bounds of <math>S</math>. A more detailed proof goes like this: Choose <math>\varepsilon=f(b)-u>0</math>. Then <math>\exists \delta>0</math> such that <math>\forall x \in [a,b]</math>, <math display="block">|x-b|<\delta \implies |f(x)-f(b)|<f(b)-u \implies f(x)>u.</math>Consider the interval <math>(\max(a,b-\delta),b]=I_2</math>. Notice that <math>I_2 \subseteq [a,b]</math> and every <math>x \in I_2</math> satisfies the condition <math>|x-b|<\delta</math>. Therefore for every <math>x \in I_2</math> we have <math>f(x)>u</math>. Hence <math>c</math> cannot be <math>b</math>. With <math>c \neq a</math> and <math>c \neq b</math>, it must be the case <math>c \in (a,b)</math>. Now we claim that <math>f(c)=u</math>. Fix some <math>\varepsilon > 0</math>. Since <math>f</math> is continuous at <math>c</math>, <math>\exists \delta_1>0</math> such that <math>\forall x \in [a,b]</math>, <math>|x-c|<\delta_1 \implies |f(x) - f(c)| < \varepsilon</math>. Since <math>c \in (a,b)</math> and <math>(a,b)</math> is open, <math>\exists \delta_2>0</math> such that <math>(c-\delta_2,c+\delta_2) \subseteq (a,b)</math>. Set <math>\delta= \min(\delta_1,\delta_2)</math>. Then we have <math display="block">f(x)-\varepsilon<f(c)<f(x)+\varepsilon</math> for all <math>x\in(c-\delta,c+\delta)</math>. By the properties of the supremum, there exists some <math>a^*\in (c-\delta,c]</math> that is contained in <math>S</math>, and so <math display="block">f(c)<f(a^*)+\varepsilon<u+\varepsilon.</math> Picking <math>a^{**}\in(c,c+\delta)</math>, we know that <math>a^{**}\not\in S</math> because <math>c</math> is the supremum of <math>S</math>. This means that <math display="block">f(c)>f(a^{**})-\varepsilon \geq u-\varepsilon.</math> Both inequalities <math display="block">u-\varepsilon<f(c)< u+\varepsilon</math> are valid for all <math>\varepsilon > 0</math>, from which we deduce <math>f(c) = u</math> as the only possible value, as stated.
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Intermediate value theorem
(section)
Add topic