Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Intellectual history
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==== Unit-idea ==== In the History of Ideas, Lovejoy used the ''unit-idea'' (concept) as the basic unit of historical analysis. The unit-idea is the building block of the history of ideas; though relatively stable in itself, the unit-idea combines with other unit-ideas into new patterns of meaning in the context of different historical eras. Lovejoy said that the historian of ideas is tasked with identifying unit-ideas and with describing their historical emergence and development into new conceptual forms and combinations. The methodology of the unit-idea means to extract the basic idea from a work of philosophy and from a philosophical movement, with the investigative principles of the methodology being: (1) assumptions, (2) dialectical motives, (3) metaphysical pathos, and (4) philosophical [[semantics]]. The principles of methodology define the overarching philosophical movement in which the historian can find the unit-idea, which then is studied throughout the history of the particular idea.<ref name="greatchain" /> The British historian [[Quentin Skinner]] criticized Lovejoy's unit-idea methodology as a "reification of doctrines" that has negative consequences.<ref>Skinner, Quentin. (1969) "Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas", ''History and Theory'' '''8''' (1): 3–53.</ref> That the historian of ideas must be sensitive to the cultural context of the texts and ideas under analysis. Skinner's [[historical method]] is based upon the theory of speech acts, proposed by [[J.L. Austin]]. In turn, scholars criticized Skinner's historical method because of his inclination to [[Reification (knowledge representation)|reify]] social structures and sociological constructs in place of the historical actors of the period under study. The philosopher [[Andreas Dorschel]] said that Skinner's restrictive approach to ideas, through verbal language, and notes that ideas can materialize in non-linguistic media and genres, such as music and architecture.<ref>Dorschel, Andreas. ''Ideengeschichte.'' Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 2010. {{ISBN|978-3-8252-3314-3}}</ref> The historian [[Dag Herbjørnsrud]] said that "the Skinner perspective is in danger of shutting the door to comparative philosophy, and the search for common problems and solutions across borders and time."<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Herbjørnsrud|first=Dag.|date=2019-05-10|title=Beyond Decolonizing: Global Intellectual History and Reconstruction of a Comparative Method|journal=Global Intellectual History|volume=6 |issue=5 |pages=614–640|doi=10.1080/23801883.2019.1616310|s2cid=166543159|issn=2380-1883}}</ref> The historian [[Peter Gordon (historian)|Peter Gordon]] said that unlike Lovejoy's practise of the History of Ideas, the praxis of Intellectual History studies and deals with ideas in broad historical contexts.<ref name="history.fas.harvard.edu">Gordon, Peter E. [http://projects.iq.harvard.edu/files/history/files/what_is_intell_history_pgordon_mar2012.pdf "What is intellectual history? A Frankly Partisan Introduction to a Frequently Misunderstood Field"]. Harvard University, Cambridge, Massachusetts.</ref> That unlike historians of ideas and philosophers ([[Philosophy#History|History of Philosophy]]), intellectual historians, "tend to be more relaxed about crossing the boundary between philosophical texts and non-philosophical contexts . . . [Intellectual historians regard] the distinction between 'philosophy' and 'non-philosophy' as something that is, itself, historically conditioned, rather than eternally fixed." Therefore, intellectual history is a means for reproducing a historically valid interpretation of a philosophical argument, by implementation of a context in which to study ideas and philosophical movements.<ref name="history.fas.harvard.edu"/>
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Intellectual history
(section)
Add topic