Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Hausdorff maximal principle
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
== Proof 1== The idea of the proof is essentially due to Zermelo and is to prove the following weak form of [[Zorn's lemma]], from the [[axiom of choice]].<ref>{{harvnb|Halmos|1960|loc=Β§ 16.}}</ref><ref>{{harvnb|Rudin|1986|loc=Appendix}}</ref> :Let <math>F</math> be a nonempty set of subsets of some fixed set, ordered by set inclusion, such that (1) the union of each totally ordered subset of <math>F</math> is in <math>F</math> and (2) each subset of a set in <math>F</math> is in <math>F</math>. Then <math>F</math> has a maximal element. (Zorn's lemma itself also follows from this weak form.) The maximal principle follows from the above since the set of all chains in <math>P</math> satisfies the above conditions. By the axiom of choice, we have a function <math>f : \mathfrak{P}(P) - \{ \emptyset \} \to P</math> such that <math>f(S) \in S</math> for the power set <math>\mathfrak{P}(P)</math> of <math>P</math>. For each <math>C \in F</math>, let <math>C^*</math> be the set of all <math>x \in P - C</math> such that <math>C \cup \{ x \}</math> is in <math>F</math>. If <math>C^* = \emptyset</math>, then let <math>\widetilde{C} = C</math>. Otherwise, let :<math>\widetilde{C} = C \cup \{ f(C^*) \}.</math> Note <math>C</math> is a maximal element if and only if <math>\widetilde{C} = C</math>. Thus, we are done if we can find a <math>C</math> such that <math>\widetilde{C} = C</math>. Fix a <math>C_0</math> in <math>F</math>. We call a subset <math>T \subset F</math> a ''tower (over <math>C_0</math>)'' if # <math>C_0</math> is in <math>T</math>. # The union of each totally ordered subset <math>T' \subset T</math> is in <math>T</math>, where "totally ordered" is with respect to set inclusion. # For each <math>C</math> in <math>T</math>, <math>\widetilde{C}</math> is in <math>T</math>. There exists at least one tower; indeed, the set of all sets in <math>F</math> containing <math>C_0</math> is a tower. Let <math>T_0</math> be the intersection of all towers, which is again a tower. Now, we shall show <math>T_0</math> is totally ordered. We say a set <math>C</math> is ''comparable in <math>T_0</math>'' if for each <math>A</math> in <math>T_0</math>, either <math>A \subset C</math> or <math>C \subset A</math>. Let <math>\Gamma</math> be the set of all sets in <math>T_0</math> that are comparable in <math>T_0</math>. We claim <math>\Gamma</math> is a tower. The conditions 1. and 2. are straightforward to check. For 3., let <math>C</math> in <math>\Gamma</math> be given and then let <math>U</math> be the set of all <math>A</math> in <math>T_0</math> such that either <math>A \subset C</math> or <math>\widetilde{C} \subset A</math>. We claim <math>U</math> is a tower. The conditions 1. and 2. are again straightforward to check. For 3., let <math>A</math> be in <math>U</math>. If <math>A \subset C</math>, then since <math>C</math> is comparable in <math>T_0</math>, either <math>\widetilde{A} \subset C</math> or <math>C \subset \widetilde{A} </math>. In the first case, <math>\widetilde{A}</math> is in <math>U</math>. In the second case, we have <math>A \subset C \subset \widetilde{A}</math>, which implies either <math>A = C</math> or <math>C = \widetilde{A}</math>. (This is the moment we needed to collapse a set to an element by the axiom of choice to define <math>\widetilde{A}</math>.) Either way, we have <math>\widetilde{A}</math> is in <math>U</math>. Similarly, if <math>C \subset A</math>, we see <math>\widetilde{A}</math> is in <math>U</math>. Hence, <math>U</math> is a tower. Now, since <math>U \subset T_0</math> and <math>T_0</math> is the intersection of all towers, <math>U = T_0</math>, which implies <math>\widetilde{C}</math> is comparable in <math>T_0</math>; i.e., is in <math>\Gamma</math>. This completes the proof of the claim that <math>\Gamma</math> is a tower. Finally, since <math>\Gamma</math> is a tower contained in <math>T_0</math>, we have <math>T_0 = \Gamma</math>, which means <math>T_0</math> is totally ordered. Let <math>C</math> be the union of <math>T_0</math>. By 2., <math>C</math> is in <math>T_0</math> and then by 3., <math>\widetilde C</math> is in <math>T_0</math>. Since <math>C</math> is the union of <math>T_0</math>, <math>\widetilde C \subset C</math> and thus <math>\widetilde C = C</math>. <math>\square</math>
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Hausdorff maximal principle
(section)
Add topic