Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Gottlob Frege
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
== Work as a logician == {{Main|Begriffsschrift}} Though his education and early mathematical work focused primarily on geometry, Frege's work soon turned to logic. His {{Citation | title = Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens | place = Halle a/S | publisher = Verlag von Louis Nebert | year = 1879 |trans-title=Concept-Script: A Formal Language for Pure Thought Modeled on that of Arithmetic| title-link = Begriffsschrift }} marked a turning point in the history of logic. The ''Begriffsschrift'' broke new ground, including a rigorous treatment of the ideas of [[function (mathematics)|functions]] and [[Variable (mathematics)|variables]]. Frege's goal was to show that mathematics grows out of [[logic]], and in so doing, he devised techniques that separated him from the Aristotelian syllogistic but took him rather close to Stoic propositional logic.<ref>[[Susanne Bobzien]] published in 2021 a work provocatively titled [https://humanities-digital-library.org/index.php/hdl/catalog/download/keeling-lectures/193/381-1?inline=1#page=171 ''"Frege plagiarized the Stoics"'']: Bobzien S., – In: ''Themes in Plato, Aristotle, and Hellenistic Philosophy'', Keeling Lectures 2011–2018, p.149-206; Zalta, Ed, [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/frege/#FrePhiLanCon ''Frege'', Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]</ref> [[File:Begriffsschrift Titel.png|thumb|Title page to ''Begriffsschrift'' (1879)]] In effect, Frege invented [[axiomatization|axiomatic]] [[predicate logic]], in large part thanks to his invention of [[Quantification (logic)|quantified variables]], which eventually became ubiquitous in [[mathematics]] and logic, and which solved the [[problem of multiple generality]]. Previous logic had dealt with the [[logical constant]]s ''and'', ''or'', ''if... then...'', ''not'', and ''some'' and ''all'', but iterations of these operations, especially "some" and "all", were little understood: even the distinction between a sentence like "every boy loves some girl" and "some girl is loved by every boy" could be represented only very artificially, whereas Frege's formalism had no difficulty expressing the different readings of "every boy loves some girl who loves some boy who loves some girl" and similar sentences, in complete parallel with his treatment of, say, "every boy is foolish". A frequently noted example is that Aristotle's logic is unable to represent mathematical statements like [[Euclid's theorem]], a fundamental statement of number theory that there are an infinite number of [[prime number]]s. Frege's "conceptual notation", however, can represent such inferences.<ref>Horsten, Leon and Pettigrew, Richard, "Introduction" in ''The Continuum Companion to Philosophical Logic'' (Continuum International Publishing Group, 2011), p. 7.</ref> The analysis of logical concepts and the machinery of formalization that is essential to ''[[Principia Mathematica]]'' (3 vols., 1910–13, by [[Bertrand Russell]], 1872–1970, and [[Alfred North Whitehead]], 1861–1947), to Russell's [[theory of descriptions]], to [[Kurt Gödel]]'s (1906–78) [[Gödel's incompleteness theorem|incompleteness theorems]], and to [[Alfred Tarski]]'s (1901–83) theory of truth, is ultimately due to Frege. One of Frege's stated purposes was to isolate genuinely logical principles of inference, so that in the proper representation of mathematical proof, one would at no point appeal to "intuition". If there was an intuitive element, it was to be isolated and represented separately as an axiom: from there on, the proof was to be purely logical and without gaps. Having exhibited this possibility, Frege's larger purpose was to defend the view that [[arithmetic]] is a branch of logic, a view known as [[logicism]]: unlike geometry, arithmetic was to be shown to have no basis in "intuition", and no need for non-logical axioms. Already in the 1879 ''Begriffsschrift'' important preliminary theorems, for example, a generalized form of [[law of trichotomy]], were derived within what Frege understood to be pure logic. This idea was formulated in non-symbolic terms in his ''[[The Foundations of Arithmetic]]'' (''Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik'', 1884). Later, in his ''Basic Laws of Arithmetic'' (''Grundgesetze der Arithmetik'', vol. 1, 1893; vol. 2, 1903; vol. 2 was published at his own expense), Frege attempted to derive, by use of his symbolism, all of the laws of arithmetic from axioms he asserted as logical. Most of these axioms were carried over from his ''[[Begriffsschrift]]'', though not without some significant changes. The one truly new principle was one he called the {{nowrap|[[Basic Law V]]}}: the "value-range" of the function ''f''(''x'') is the same as the "value-range" of the function ''g''(''x'') if and only if ∀''x''[''f''(''x'') = ''g''(''x'')]. The crucial case of the law may be formulated in modern notation as follows. Let {''x''|''Fx''} denote the [[extension (predicate logic)|extension]] of the [[Predicate (logic)|predicate]] ''Fx'', that is, the set of all Fs, and similarly for ''Gx''. Then Basic Law V says that the predicates ''Fx'' and ''Gx'' have the same extension [[if and only if]] ∀x[''Fx'' ↔ ''Gx'']. The set of Fs is the same as the set of Gs just in case every F is a G and every G is an F. (The case is special because what is here being called the extension of a predicate, or a set, is only one type of "value-range" of a function.) In a famous episode, Bertrand Russell wrote to Frege, just as Vol. 2 of the ''Grundgesetze'' was about to go to press in 1903, showing that [[Russell's paradox]] could be derived from Frege's Basic Law V. It is easy to define the relation of ''membership'' of a set or extension in Frege's system; Russell then drew attention to "the set of things ''x'' that are such that ''x'' is not a member of ''x''". The system of the ''Grundgesetze'' entails that the set thus characterised ''both'' is ''and'' is not a member of itself, and is thus inconsistent. Frege wrote a hasty, last-minute Appendix to Vol. 2, deriving the contradiction and proposing to eliminate it by modifying Basic Law V. Frege opened the Appendix with the exceptionally honest comment: "Hardly anything more unfortunate can befall a scientific writer than to have one of the foundations of his edifice shaken after the work is finished. This was the position I was placed in by a letter of Mr. Bertrand Russell, just when the printing of this volume was nearing its completion." (This letter and Frege's reply are translated in [[Jean van Heijenoort]] 1967.) Frege's proposed remedy was subsequently shown to imply that there is but one object in the [[universe of discourse]], and hence is worthless (indeed, this would make for a contradiction in Frege's system if he had axiomatized the idea, fundamental to his discussion, that the True and the False are distinct objects; see, for example, [[Michael Dummett|Dummett]] 1973), but recent work has shown that much of the program of the ''Grundgesetze'' might be salvaged in other ways: * Basic Law V can be weakened in other ways. The best-known way is due to philosopher and mathematical logician [[George Boolos]] (1940–1996), who was an expert on the work of Frege. A "concept" ''F'' is "small" if the objects falling under ''F'' cannot be put into one-to-one correspondence with the universe of discourse, that is, unless: ∃''R''[''R'' is 1-to-1 & ∀''x''∃''y''(''xRy'' & ''Fy'')]. Now weaken V to V*: a "concept" ''F'' and a "concept" ''G'' have the same "extension" if and only if neither ''F'' nor ''G'' is small or ∀''x''(''Fx'' ↔ ''Gx''). V* is consistent if [[second-order arithmetic]] is, and suffices to prove the axioms of second-order arithmetic. * Basic Law V can simply be replaced with [[Hume's principle]], which says that the number of ''F''s is the same as the number of ''G''s if and only if the ''F''s can be put into a one-to-one correspondence with the ''G''s. This principle, too, is consistent if second-order arithmetic is, and suffices to prove the axioms of second-order arithmetic. This result is termed [[Frege's theorem]] because it was noticed that in developing arithmetic, Frege's use of Basic Law V is restricted to a proof of Hume's principle; it is from this, in turn, that arithmetical principles are derived. On Hume's principle and Frege's theorem, see "Frege's Logic, Theorem, and Foundations for Arithmetic".<ref>[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/frege-logic/ Frege's Logic, Theorem, and Foundations for Arithmetic, ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy''] at plato.stanford.edu</ref> * Frege's logic, now known as [[second-order logic]], can be weakened to so-called [[Impredicativity|predicative]] second-order logic. Predicative second-order logic plus Basic Law V is provably consistent by [[finitism|finitistic]] or [[Mathematical constructivism|constructive]] methods, but it can interpret only very weak fragments of arithmetic.<ref>{{cite book|author=Burgess, John|title=Fixing Frege|year=2005|publisher=Princeton University Press |isbn=978-0-691-12231-1}}</ref> Frege's work in logic had little international attention until 1903, when Russell wrote an appendix to ''[[The Principles of Mathematics]]'' stating his differences with Frege. The diagrammatic notation that Frege used had no antecedents (and has had no imitators since). Moreover, until Russell and Whitehead's ''[[Principia Mathematica]]'' (3 vols.) appeared in 1910–13, the dominant approach to [[mathematical logic]] was still that of [[George Boole]] (1815–64) and his intellectual descendants, especially [[Ernst Schröder (mathematician)|Ernst Schröder]] (1841–1902). Frege's logical ideas nevertheless spread through the writings of his student [[Rudolf Carnap]] (1891–1970) and other admirers, particularly Bertrand Russell<ref name="Klement_20230617">{{cite web |title=Peano, Frege, and Russell's Logical Influences|first=Kevin C. |last=Klement|date=June 17, 2023|url=https://philarchive.org/archive/KLEPFA-3 |access-date=April 26, 2025}}</ref>{{rp|2}} and [[Ludwig Wittgenstein]] (1889–1951).<ref name="Burge_2013">{{cite book |editor-first=Michael |editor-last=Beaney |title=The Oxford Handbook of The History of Analytic Philosophy|location=Oxford, England |publisher=Oxford University Press |date=2013|author=[[Tyler Burge]] |chapter=Chapter 10: Gottlob Frege: Some forms of influence |pages=355–382 |access-date=April 26, 2025|chapter-url=https://philosophy.ucla.edu/wp-content/uploads/2018/08/Burge-2013-Frege-Some-Forms-of-Influence.pdf}}</ref>{{rp|357}}
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Gottlob Frege
(section)
Add topic