Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Goodstein's theorem
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
=== Extended Goodstein's theorem === The above proof still works if the definition of the Goodstein sequence is changed so that the base-changing operation replaces each occurrence of the base <math>b</math> with <math>b+2</math> instead of <math>b+1</math>. More generally, let <math>b_1</math>, <math>b_2</math>, <math>b_3, \ldots</math> be any non-decreasing sequence of integers with <math>b_1 \geq 2</math>. Then let the <math>(n+1)</math>st term <math>G_m(n+1)</math> of the extended Goodstein sequence of <math>m</math> be as follows: * Take the hereditary base <math>b_n</math> representation of <math>G_m(n)</math>. * Replace each occurrence of the base <math>b_n</math> with <math>b_{n+1}</math>. * Subtract one. A simple modification of the above proof shows that this sequence still terminates. For example, if <math>b_n = 4</math> and if <math>b_{n+1} = 9</math>, then <math>f(3 \cdot 4^{4^4} + 4, 4) = 3 \omega^{\omega^\omega} + \omega= f(3 \cdot 9^{9^9} + 9, 9)</math>, hence the ordinal <math>f(3 \cdot 4^{4^4} + 4, 4)</math> is strictly greater than the ordinal <math>f\big((3 \cdot 9^{9^9} + 9) - 1, 9\big).</math> The extended version is in fact the one considered in Goodstein's original paper,{{sfn|Goodstein|1944}} where Goodstein proved that it is equivalent to the restricted ordinal theorem (i.e. the claim that [[transfinite induction]] below [[Epsilon numbers (mathematics)|ε<sub>0</sub>]] is valid), and gave a [[finitist]] proof for the case where <math>m \le b_1^{b_1^{b_1}}</math> (equivalent to transfinite induction up to <math>\omega^{\omega^\omega}</math>). The extended Goodstein's theorem without any restriction on the sequence ''b<sub>n</sub>'' is not formalizable in Peano arithmetic (PA), since such an arbitrary infinite sequence cannot be represented in PA. This seems to be what kept Goodstein from claiming back in 1944 that the extended Goodstein's theorem is unprovable in PA due to [[Gödel's second incompleteness theorem]] and Gentzen's proof of the consistency of PA using ε<sub>0</sub>-induction.{{sfn|Rathjen|2014}} However, inspection of Gentzen's proof shows that it only needs the fact that there is no [[primitive recursive]] strictly decreasing infinite sequence of ordinals, so limiting ''b<sub>n</sub>'' to primitive recursive sequences would have allowed Goodstein to prove an unprovability result.{{sfn|Rathjen|2014}} Furthermore, with the relatively elementary technique of the [[Grzegorczyk hierarchy]], it can be shown that every primitive recursive strictly decreasing infinite sequence of ordinals can be "slowed down" so that it can be transformed to a Goodstein sequence where <math>b_n = n+1</math>, thus giving an alternative proof to the same result Kirby and Paris proved.{{sfn|Rathjen|2014}}
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Goodstein's theorem
(section)
Add topic