Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Zeno's paradoxes
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
=== Paradoxes of motion === Three of the strongest and most famous—that of Achilles and the tortoise, the [[Dichotomy]] argument, and that of an arrow in flight—are presented in detail below. ==== Dichotomy paradox ==== [[File:Zeno Dichotomy Paradox alt.png|thumb|The dichotomy]] {{ quote | That which is in locomotion must arrive at the half-way stage before it arrives at the goal.| as recounted by [[Aristotle]], [[Physics (Aristotle)|''Physics'']] VI:9, 239b10 }} Suppose [[Atalanta]] wishes to walk to the end of a path. Before she can get there, she must get halfway there. Before she can get halfway there, she must get a quarter of the way there. Before traveling a quarter, she must travel one-eighth; before an eighth, one-sixteenth; and so on. <timeline> ImageSize= width:800 height:100 PlotArea= width:720 height:55 left:65 bottom:20 AlignBars= justify Period= from:0 till:100 TimeAxis= orientation:horizontal ScaleMajor= unit:year increment:10 start:0 ScaleMinor= unit:year increment:1 start:0 Colors= id:homer value:rgb(0.4,0.8,1) # light purple PlotData= bar:homer fontsize:L color:homer from:0 till:100 at:50 mark:(line,red) at:25 mark:(line,black) at:12.5 mark:(line,black) at:6.25 mark:(line,black) at:3.125 mark:(line,black) at:1.5625 mark:(line,black) at:0.78125 mark:(line,black) at:0.390625 mark:(line,black) at:0.1953125 mark:(line,black) at:0.09765625 mark:(line,black) </timeline> The resulting sequence can be represented as: :<math> \left\{ \cdots, \frac{1}{16}, \frac{1}{8}, \frac{1}{4}, \frac{1}{2}, 1 \right\}</math> This description requires one to complete an infinite number of tasks, which Zeno maintains is an impossibility.<ref>{{cite book|last1=Lindberg|first1=David|title=The Beginnings of Western Science|date=2007|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0-226-48205-7|page=33|edition=2nd}}</ref> This sequence also presents a second problem in that it contains no first distance to run, for any possible ([[wikt:finite|finite]]) first distance could be divided in half, and hence would not be first after all. Hence, the trip cannot even begin. The paradoxical conclusion then would be that travel over any finite distance can be neither completed nor begun, and so all motion must be an [[illusion]].<ref>{{cite encyclopedia |last=Huggett |first=Nick |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/paradox-zeno/#Dic |title=Zeno's Paradoxes: 3.1 The Dichotomy |year=2010 |encyclopedia=[[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]] |access-date=2011-03-07 |archive-date=2022-03-01 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220301174333/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/paradox-zeno/#Dic |url-status=live }}</ref> This argument is called the "[[Dichotomy]]" because it involves repeatedly splitting a distance into two parts. An example with the original sense can be found in an [[asymptote]]. It is also known as the '''Race Course''' paradox. ==== Achilles and the tortoise<!--'Achilles and the Tortoise' and 'Achilles and the tortoise' redirects here--> ==== {{Redirect|Achilles and the Tortoise}} {{See also|Infinity#Zeno: Achilles and the tortoise|selfref=yes}} [[File:Zeno Achilles Paradox.png|thumb|Achilles and the tortoise]] {{ quote | In a race, the quickest runner can never over­take the slowest, since the pursuer must first reach the point whence the pursued started, so that the slower must always hold a lead.| as recounted by [[Aristotle]], [[Physics (Aristotle)|''Physics'']] VI:9, 239b15 }} In the paradox of '''Achilles and the tortoise'''<!--boldface per WP:R#PLA-->, [[Achilles]] is in a footrace with a tortoise. Achilles allows the tortoise a head start of 100 meters, for example. Suppose that each racer starts running at some constant speed, one faster than the other. After some finite time, Achilles will have run 100 meters, bringing him to the tortoise's starting point. During this time, the tortoise has run a much shorter distance, say 2 meters. It will then take Achilles some further time to run that distance, by which time the tortoise will have advanced farther; and then more time still to reach this third point, while the tortoise moves ahead. Thus, whenever Achilles arrives somewhere the tortoise has been, he still has some distance to go before he can even reach the tortoise. As Aristotle noted, this argument is similar to the Dichotomy.<ref>{{cite encyclopedia |last=Huggett |first=Nick |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/paradox-zeno/#AchTor |title=Zeno's Paradoxes: 3.2 Achilles and the Tortoise |year=2010 |encyclopedia=[[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]] |access-date=2011-03-07 |archive-date=2022-03-01 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220301174333/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/paradox-zeno/#AchTor |url-status=live }}</ref> It lacks, however, the apparent conclusion of motionlessness. ==== Arrow paradox ==== {{distinct|text = [[Arrow paradox (disambiguation)|''other paradoxes of the same name'']]}} [[File:Zeno Arrow Paradox.png|thumb|The arrow]] {{quote|If everything when it occupies an equal space is at rest at that instant of time, and if that which is in locomotion is always occupying such a space at any moment, the flying arrow is therefore motionless at that instant of time and at the next instant of time but if both instants of time are taken as the same instant or continuous instant of time then it is in motion.<ref>{{cite web |url=http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/physics.6.vi.html#752 |work=The Internet Classics Archive |title=Physics |author=Aristotle |quote=Zeno's reasoning, however, is fallacious, when he says that if everything when it occupies an equal space is at rest, and if that which is in locomotion is always occupying such a space at any moment, the flying arrow is therefore motionless. This is false, for time is not composed of indivisible moments any more than any other magnitude is composed of indivisibles. |access-date=2012-08-21 |archive-date=2008-05-15 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20080515224131/http://classics.mit.edu//Aristotle/physics.6.vi.html#752 |url-status=live }}</ref>|as recounted by [[Aristotle]], [[Physics (Aristotle)|''Physics'']] VI:9, 239b5|title=|source=}} In the arrow paradox, Zeno states that for motion to occur, an object must change the position which it occupies. He gives an example of an arrow in flight. He states that at any one (durationless) instant of time, the arrow is neither moving to where it is, nor to where it is not.<ref>{{cite book | chapter-url=http://en.wikisource.org/wiki/Lives_of_the_Eminent_Philosophers/Book_IX#Pyrrho | first=Diogenes | last=Laërtius | author-link=Diogenes Laërtius | title=Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers | volume=IX | chapter=Pyrrho | at=passage 72 | year=2009 |orig-date=c. 230 | isbn=1-116-71900-2 | title-link=Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers | publisher=BiblioBazaar | access-date=2011-03-05 | archive-date=2011-08-22 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110822084058/http://en.wikisource.org/wiki/Lives_of_the_Eminent_Philosophers/Book_IX#Pyrrho | url-status=live }}</ref> It cannot move to where it is not, because no time elapses for it to move there; it cannot move to where it is, because it is already there. In other words, at every instant of time there is no motion occurring. If everything is motionless at every instant, and time is entirely composed of instants, then motion is impossible. Whereas the first two paradoxes divide space, this paradox starts by dividing time—and not into segments, but into points.<ref name=HuggettArrow>{{cite encyclopedia |last=Huggett |first=Nick |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/paradox-zeno/#Arr |title=Zeno's Paradoxes: 3.3 The Arrow |year=2010 |encyclopedia=[[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]] |access-date=2011-03-07 |archive-date=2022-03-01 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220301174333/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/paradox-zeno/#Arr |url-status=live }}</ref>
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Zeno's paradoxes
(section)
Add topic