Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Syllogism
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Syllogistic fallacies== People often make mistakes when reasoning syllogistically.<ref>See, e.g., Evans, J. St. B. T (1989). ''Bias in human reasoning''. London: LEA.</ref> For instance, from the premises some A are B, some B are C, people tend to come to a definitive conclusion that therefore some A are C.<ref>Khemlani, S., and P. N. Johnson-Laird. 2012. "Theories of the syllogism: A meta-analysis." ''[[Psychological Bulletin]]'' 138:427β57.</ref><ref>Chater, N., and M. Oaksford. 1999. "The Probability Heuristics Model of Syllogistic Reasoning." ''[[Cognitive Psychology (journal)|Cognitive Psychology]]'' 38:191β258.</ref> However, this does not follow according to the rules of classical logic. For instance, while some cats (A) are black things (B), and some black things (B) are televisions (C), it does not follow from the parameters that some cats (A) are televisions (C). This is because in the structure of the syllogism invoked (i.e. III-1) the middle term is not distributed in either the major premise or in the minor premise, a pattern called the "[[fallacy of the undistributed middle]]". Because of this, it can be hard to follow formal logic, and a closer eye is needed in order to ensure that an argument is, in fact, valid.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Lundberg|first=Christian|title=The Essential Guide to Rhetoric|publisher=Bedford/St. Martin's|year=2018|pages=39}}</ref> Determining the validity of a syllogism involves determining the [[distribution of terms|distribution]] of each term in each statement, meaning whether all members of that term are accounted for. In simple syllogistic patterns, the fallacies of invalid patterns are: *[[Fallacy of the undistributed middle|Undistributed middle]]: Neither of the premises accounts for all members of the middle term, which consequently fails to link the major and minor term. *[[Illicit major|Illicit treatment of the major term]]: The conclusion implicates all members of the major term (P β meaning the proposition is negative); however, the major premise does not account for them all (i.e., P is either an affirmative predicate or a particular subject there). *[[Illicit minor|Illicit treatment of the minor term]]: Same as above, but for the minor term (S β meaning the proposition is universal) and minor premise (where S is either a particular subject or an affirmative predicate). *[[Fallacy of exclusive premises|Exclusive premises]]: Both premises are negative, meaning no link is established between the major and minor terms. *[[Affirmative conclusion from a negative premise]]: If either premise is negative, the conclusion must also be. *[[Negative conclusion from affirmative premises]]: If both premises are affirmative, the conclusion must also be.
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Syllogism
(section)
Add topic