Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Nihilism
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
== Ethics and value theory == [[File:Nietzsche1882.jpg|thumb|alt=Black-and-white photo showing a man with a thick mustache from the side, wearing a dark suit and resting is his head on his hand|[[Friedrich Nietzsche]] described nihilism as the process in which "the highest values devaluate themselves".<ref>{{harvnb|Slocombe|2006|p=1}}</ref>]] Various forms of nihilism belong to the fields of [[ethics]] and [[value theory]], questioning the existence of values, [[morality]], and the [[meaning of life]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Gemes|Sykes|2013|p=671}} | {{harvnb|Pratt|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Cowan|2020|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=_2jDDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA25 25]}} | {{harvnb|Oddie|2013|loc=Β§ Are Value Claims Truth Evaluable?, Β§ Quasi-Realism and Creeping Minimalism}} | {{harvnb|Groothuis|2020|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=_2jDDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA165 165β169]}} }}</ref> === Existential nihilism === {{main|Existential nihilism}} Existential nihilism asserts that life is meaningless. It is not limited to the idea that some people fail to find meaning in their lives but makes the broader claim that human existence in general or the world as a whole lacks a higher purpose. This view suggests that it is not possible to live a genuinely meaningful life, that there is no higher reason to continue living, and that all efforts, achievements, happiness, and suffering are ultimately pointless.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Pratt|loc=Β§ 3. Existential Nihilism}} | {{harvnb|Crosby|1998|loc=Β§ Existential Nihilism}} | {{harvnb|Groothuis|2020|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=_2jDDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA165 165β169]}} }}</ref> Existential nihilism has diverse practical implications since people usually act with a purpose in mind, sometimes with the explicit goal of making their lives meaningful. As a result, the belief that there is no higher meaning or purpose can bring about [[Apathy|indifference]], a [[Motivation#Amotivation_and_akrasia|lack of motivation]], and [[anxiety]]. In extreme cases, this can result in [[Depression (mood)|depression]] and despair or trigger an [[existential crisis]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Joyce|2013}} | {{harvnb|Tartaglia|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=acazCgAAQBAJ&pg=PA25 25β27]}} | {{harvnb|Yalom|2020|pp=423β428}} | {{harvnb|Sommers-Flanagan|Sommers-Flanagan|2012|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=RMclh6zR3LEC&pg=PA131 131]}} }}</ref>{{efn|Existential crises are inner conflicts in which individuals struggle to find meaning in their lifes. Some authors suggest that nihilistic beliefs can trigger existential crises. Others propose nihilism as one way to resolve them by learning to accept meaninglessness rather than finding a source of meaning.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Carr|1992|pp=125β126}} | {{harvnb|Yalom|2020|pp=423β428}} | {{harvnb|Davis|Hicks|2013|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=HcxEAAAAQBAJ&pg=PA166 166, 171β172 ]}} | {{harvnb|American Psychological Association|2023}} }}</ref>}} Some philosophers, such as [[Martin Heidegger]] (1889β1976), highlight the connection to [[boredom]], arguing that the lack of engagement and goals experienced in this [[Mood (psychology)|mood]] makes life appear pointless.<ref>{{harvnb|Tartaglia|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=acazCgAAQBAJ&pg=PA25 25β27]}}</ref> [[File:Flickr - Government Press Office (GPO) - Jean Paul Sartre and Simone De Beauvoir welcomed by Avraham Shlonsky and Leah Goldberg (cropped).jpg|thumb|alt=Black-and-white photo of a man with glasses wearing a dark suit with a tie|Considering the problem of existential nihilism, [[Jean Paul Sartre]] proposed that people can make their lives meaningful by inventing themselves and their values.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crosby|1998|loc=Β§ 3. Existential nihilism}} | {{harvnb|Gertz|2019|pp=82β85}} }}</ref>]] Various possible reactions to existential nihilism have been proposed.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Tartaglia|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=acazCgAAQBAJ&pg=PA41 41β42]}} | {{harvnb|Crosby|1998|loc=Β§ Existential Nihilism}} }}</ref> Inspired by [[Indian philosophy]], [[Arthur Schopenhauer]] (1788β1860) suggested a [[Philosophical pessimism|pessimistic]] and [[ascetic]] response, advocating detachment from the world by [[Renunciation|renouncing]] desires and stopping to affirm life.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crosby|1998|loc=Β§ Existential Nihilism}} | {{harvnb|Stewart|2023|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=oImzEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA147 147]}} }}</ref> [[Friedrich Nietzsche]] (1844β1900) proposed using the disruptive force of nihilism to [[Transvaluation of values|re-interpret or re-evaluate all established ideals and values]] in an attempt to overcome nihilism and replace it with an [[Nietzschean affirmation|affirmative attitude toward life]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Pratt|loc=Lead section, Β§ 2. Friedrich Nietzsche and Nihilism}} | {{harvnb|Diken|2008|pp=5, 31}} }}</ref>{{efn|In this context, Nietzsche contrasted passive with active nihilism. Passive nihilism is a form of resignation characterized by pessimism, hopelessness, and disengagement while refusing to acknowledge the absence of meaning. Active nihilism openly accepts meaninglessness and uses its negativity as a force to destroy established values and ideologies.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Vattimo|1989|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=G-1YV3x6yakC&pg=PA15 15β17]}} | {{harvnb|Gillespie|1996|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=r4Itb0Zc2hUC&pg=PA179 179β180]}} }}</ref>}} [[Jean-Paul Sartre]] (1905β1980) suggested that people can create their own values through the free choices they make, despite the cosmic lack of meaning. After considering the possibility of committing suicide, [[Albert Camus]] (1913β1960) argued instead for a defiant attitude in which individuals rebel against meaninglessness.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crosby|1998|loc=Β§ Existential Nihilism}} | {{harvnb|Pratt|loc=Β§ 3. Existential Nihilism}} | {{harvnb|Joyce|2013}} }}</ref> Other responses include a destructive attitude aiming to violently tear down political authorities and social institutions, attempts to undermine nihilism by identifying genuine sources of meaning, and a passive [[resignation]] or quiet acceptance.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Diken|2008|pp=3β4, 15β16, 28}} | {{harvnb|Tartaglia|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=acazCgAAQBAJ&pg=PA48 48β49]}} }}</ref> Various arguments for and against existential nihilism are discussed in the academic discourse. Arguments from a [[cosmological]] perspective assert that human existence is a minor and insignificant aspect of the [[universe]] as a whole, which is indifferent to human concerns and aspirations. This outlook aligns with an [[atheistic]] view, stating that, without a God, there is no source of higher values that transcend the natural world. Another viewpoint highlights the pervasiveness of senseless suffering and violence while emphasizing the fleeting nature of happiness. Some theorists link this view to human mortality, suggesting that the inevitability of [[death]] renders all human accomplishments transient and ultimately futile.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crosby|1998|loc=Β§ Critical comment}} | {{harvnb|Crosby|1988|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=9VnPgFiW0CIC&pg=PA38 38β40, 46β47, 53, 55β58]}} | {{harvnb|Tartaglia|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=acazCgAAQBAJ&pg=PA21 21β25]}} | {{harvnb|Stewart|2023|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=oImzEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA2 2β4]}} | {{harvnb|Gertz|2019|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=aU6qDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA81 81, 87]}} }}</ref> A different perspective from biology argues that life is driven by blind [[natural selection]] on a large scale and the satisfaction of innate [[need]]s on an individual scale, neither of which aims at a higher purpose.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crosby|1998|loc=Β§ Critical comment}} | {{harvnb|Tartaglia|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=acazCgAAQBAJ&pg=PA21 21β22]}} }}</ref> Subjectivists, by contrast, focus on the [[Subjectivity and objectivity (philosophy)|subjective]] nature of all value experiences, asserting that they lack any objective ground.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crosby|1998|loc=Β§ Critical comment}} | {{harvnb|Crosby|1988|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=9VnPgFiW0CIC&pg=PA41 41β42]}} }}</ref> Opponents of existential nihilism have responded with counterarguments to these statements. For example, some reject the pessimistic outlook that life is primarily characterized by suffering, violence, and death, claiming instead that these negative phenomena are counterbalanced by positive phenomena such as happiness and love.<ref>{{harvnb|Crosby|1988|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=9VnPgFiW0CIC&pg=PA352 352β357]}}</ref> Many non-nihilistic theories of the meaning of life are examined in the academic discourse. [[Supernaturalistic]] views focus on God or the soul as sources of meaning. [[Ethical naturalism|Naturalistic]] views, by contrast, assert that subjective or objective values are inherent in the physical world. They include the discussion of fields where humans actively find meaning, such as exercising [[freedom]], committing oneself to a cause, pursuing [[altruism]], and engaging in positive [[social relationships]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crosby|1988|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=9VnPgFiW0CIC&pg=PA364 364β367, 369β370]}} | {{harvnb|Metz|2023|loc=Β§ 2. Supernaturalism, Β§ 3. Naturalism}} | {{harvnb|Seachris|loc=Β§ 3. Theories of Meaning ''in'' Life}} | {{harvnb|Yalom|2020|pp=431β435}} }}</ref> === Moral nihilism === {{main|Moral nihilism}} Unlike existential nihilism, moral nihilism focuses specifically on moral phenomena rather than a higher meaning or purpose. In its broadest form, it is the [[metaethics|metaethical]] view that there are no moral facts. Also called ''amoralism'' and ''error theory'', it denies the objective existence of morality, arguing that the theories and practices categorized under this label rest on misguided assumptions without any substantial link to reality.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crosby|1988|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=9VnPgFiW0CIC&pg=PA11 11β12]}} | {{harvnb|Joyce|2013}} | {{harvnb|Gemes|Sykes|2013|p=673}} | {{harvnb|Dreier|2007|pp=240β242}} }}</ref> On a practical level, some moral nihilists, such as [[Friedrich Nietzsche]], conclude from this observation that anything is permitted, suggesting that people are allowed to act however they want without any social restrictions. Other moral nihilists reject this conclusion and argue that the denial of morality affects not only moral obligations, or what people are required to do, but also moral permissions, or what people are allowed to do.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Dreier|2007|pp=240β242}} | {{harvnb|Krellenstein|2017|pp=[https://www.jstor.org/stable/44631529 75β90]}} | {{harvnb|Joyce|2013}} | {{harvnb|Gemes|Sykes|2013|p=673}} }}</ref> Axiological nihilism, a related view, denies the objective existence of values in general. This rejection is not limited to moral values and also concerns other types, like aesthetic and religious values.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Mulligan|2009|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=Bt99AgAAQBAJ&pg=PA401 401β402]}} | {{harvnb|Oddie|2013|loc=Lead section, Β§ Do Value Claims Have Truth Makers?}} }}</ref> One motivation for denying the existence of morality rests on the idea that moral properties are odd compared to other properties, like shape and size. This view is sometimes combined with the claim that scientific inquiry does not reveal objective moral facts or that humans lack a [[Epistemology#Sources|source]] of moral knowledge. A related argument for moral nihilism focuses on the conventional aspects of moral evaluations and the difficulties in resolving moral disagreements.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Gemes|Sykes|2013|p=673}} | {{harvnb|Dreier|2007|pp=242β249}} | {{harvnb|Krellenstein|2017|pp=76β80}} }}</ref> Another line of thought emphasizes the [[evolution]]ary origin of morality, viewing it as a mere product of natural selection without a deeper metaphysical foundation.<ref>{{harvnb|Krellenstein|2017|pp=76β80}}</ref> [[Moral realism|Moral realists]] have raised various objections to moral nihilism. Naturalists argue that moral facts belong to the natural world and can be empirically observed. [[Ethical non-naturalism|Non-naturalists]] assert that moral phenomena are different from natural phenomena, but are real nonetheless.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Sayre-McCord|2023|loc=Β§ 2. Metaphysics}} | {{harvnb|Lutz|2023|loc=Lead section, Β§ 1. What Is Moral Naturalism?}} | {{harvnb|DeLapp|loc=Β§ 4a. Moral Realisms}} | {{harvnb|FitzPatrick|2011|pp=[https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1057/9780230294899_2 7β8]}} | {{harvnb|Ridge|2019|loc=Lead section}} }}</ref> Another perspective highlights the deep gap between moral nihilism and the fields of [[common sense]] and moral experience. Some viewpoints emphasize the negative practical consequences of abandoning moral beliefs or assert that moral nihilism is incoherent because it rests on a misunderstanding of moral language.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Sinnott-Armstrong|2007|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=5pzCOHmcDocC&pg=PA59 53β59]}} | {{harvnb|Krellenstein|2017|pp=80β82}} }}</ref> The term ''moral nihilism'' is sometimes used with a different meaning. In one sense, it is the same as moral subjectivism, arguing that moral evaluations are purely subjective and lack rational objective justification. As a result, moral judgments are seen as [[Expressivism|expressions of arbitrary individual preferences]], which vary between individuals, making moral disagreements rationally unresolvable.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crosby|1988|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=9VnPgFiW0CIC&pg=PA11 11β14]}} | {{harvnb|Weller|2010|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=TEZ9DAAAQBAJ&pg=PA10 10]}} }}</ref> In another sense, moral nihilism refers to [[ethical egoism]], the theory that morality is determined by self-interest. This view denies that the [[well-being]] of others has moral implications unless it has external consequences for one's own well-being.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crosby|1988|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=9VnPgFiW0CIC&pg=PA11 11, 14β15]}} | {{harvnb|Weller|2010|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=TEZ9DAAAQBAJ&pg=PA10 10]}} }}</ref>
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Nihilism
(section)
Add topic