Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Cox's theorem
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Implications of Cox's postulates== The laws of probability derivable from these postulates are the following.<ref name="Jaynes2003">[[Edwin Thompson Jaynes]], ''Probability Theory: The Logic of Science,'' Cambridge University Press (2003). — preprint version (1996) at {{cite web |url=http://omega.albany.edu:8008/JaynesBook.html |title=Archived copy |access-date=2016-01-19 |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160119131820/http://omega.albany.edu:8008/JaynesBook.html |archive-date=2016-01-19 }}; Chapters 1 to 3 of published version at http://bayes.wustl.edu/etj/prob/book.pdf </ref> Let <math>A\mid B</math> be the plausibility of the proposition <math>A</math> given <math>B</math> satisfying Cox's postulates. Then there is a function <math>w</math> mapping plausibilities to interval [0,1] and a positive number <math>m</math> such that # Certainty is represented by <math>w(A\mid B)=1.</math> # <math>w^m(A|B)+w^m(\text{not }A\mid B)=1.</math> # <math>w(AB\mid C)=w(A\mid C)w(B\mid AC)=w(B\mid C)w(A\mid BC).</math> It is important to note that the postulates imply only these general properties. We may recover the usual laws of probability by setting a new function, conventionally denoted <math>P</math> or <math>\Pr</math>, equal to <math>w^m</math>. Then we obtain the laws of probability in a more familiar form: # Certain truth is represented by <math>\Pr(A\mid B)=1</math>, and certain falsehood by <math>\Pr(A\mid B)=0.</math> # <math>\Pr(A\mid B)+\Pr(\text{not }A\mid B)=1.</math> # <math>\Pr(AB\mid C)=\Pr(A\mid C)\Pr(B\mid AC)=\Pr(B\mid C)\Pr(A\mid BC).</math> Rule 2 is a rule for negation, and rule 3 is a rule for conjunction. Given that any proposition containing conjunction, [[disjunction]], and negation can be equivalently rephrased using conjunction and negation alone (the [[conjunctive normal form]]), we can now handle any compound proposition. The laws thus derived yield [[Measure (mathematics)|finite additivity]] of probability, but not [[Measure (mathematics)|countable additivity]]. The [[Probability axioms|measure-theoretic formulation of Kolmogorov]] assumes that a probability measure is countably additive. This slightly stronger condition is necessary for certain results. An elementary example (in which this assumption merely simplifies the calculation rather than being necessary for it) is that the probability of seeing heads for the first time after an even number of flips in a sequence of coin flips is <math>\tfrac13</math>.<ref>{{citation | last = Price | first = David T. | doi = 10.2307/2319450 | journal = American Mathematical Monthly | jstor = 2319450 | mr = 350798 | pages = 886β889 | title = Countable additivity for probability measures | volume = 81 | year = 1974| issue = 8 }}</ref>
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Cox's theorem
(section)
Add topic