Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Compactness theorem
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Applications== The compactness theorem has many applications in model theory; a few typical results are sketched here. ===Robinson's principle=== The compactness theorem implies the following result, stated by [[Abraham Robinson]] in his 1949 dissertation. [[Robinson's principle]]:{{sfn|Marker|2002|pp=40-43}}{{sfn|Gowers|Barrow-Green|Leader|2008|pp=639-643}} If a first-order sentence holds in every [[Field (mathematics)|field]] of [[Characteristic (algebra)|characteristic]] zero, then there exists a constant <math>p</math> such that the sentence holds for every field of characteristic larger than <math>p.</math> This can be seen as follows: suppose <math>\varphi</math> is a sentence that holds in every field of characteristic zero. Then its negation <math>\lnot \varphi,</math> together with the field axioms and the infinite sequence of sentences <math display=block>1 + 1 \neq 0, \;\; 1 + 1 + 1 \neq 0, \; \ldots</math> is not [[Satisfiability|satisfiable]] (because there is no field of characteristic 0 in which <math>\lnot \varphi</math> holds, and the infinite sequence of sentences ensures any model would be a field of characteristic 0). Therefore, there is a finite subset <math>A</math> of these sentences that is not satisfiable. <math>A</math> must contain <math>\lnot \varphi</math> because otherwise it would be satisfiable. Because adding more sentences to <math>A</math> does not change unsatisfiability, we can assume that <math>A</math> contains the field axioms and, for some <math>k,</math> the first <math>k</math> sentences of the form <math>1 + 1 + \cdots + 1 \neq 0.</math> Let <math>B</math> contain all the sentences of <math>A</math> except <math>\lnot \varphi.</math> Then any field with a characteristic greater than <math>k</math> is a model of <math>B,</math> and <math>\lnot \varphi</math> together with <math>B</math> is not satisfiable. This means that <math>\varphi</math> must hold in every model of <math>B,</math> which means precisely that <math>\varphi</math> holds in every field of characteristic greater than <math>k.</math> This completes the proof. The [[Lefschetz principle]], one of the first examples of a [[transfer principle]], extends this result. A first-order sentence <math>\varphi</math> in the language of [[Ring (mathematics)|rings]] is true in {{em|some}} (or equivalently, in {{em|every}}) [[algebraically closed]] field of characteristic 0 (such as the [[complex number]]s for instance) if and only if there exist infinitely many primes <math>p</math> for which <math>\varphi</math> is true in {{em|some}} algebraically closed field of characteristic <math>p,</math> in which case <math>\varphi</math> is true in {{em|all}} algebraically closed fields of sufficiently large non-0 characteristic <math>p.</math>{{sfn|Marker|2002|pp=40-43}} One consequence is the following special case of the [[Ax–Grothendieck theorem]]: all [[injective map|injective]] [[Complex number|complex]] [[polynomial]]s <math>\Complex^n \to \Complex^n</math> are [[Surjective map|surjective]]{{sfn|Marker|2002|pp=40-43}} (indeed, it can even be shown that its inverse will also be a polynomial).<ref name=Tao2009AxGrothendieck>{{cite web|last=Terence|first=Tao|title=Infinite fields, finite fields, and the Ax-Grothendieck theorem|date=7 March 2009|url=https://terrytao.wordpress.com/2009/03/07/infinite-fields-finite-fields-and-the-ax-grothendieck-theorem/}}</ref> In fact, the surjectivity conclusion remains true for any injective polynomial <math>F^n \to F^n</math> where <math>F</math> is a finite field or the algebraic closure of such a field.<ref name=Tao2009AxGrothendieck /> ===Upward Löwenheim–Skolem theorem=== A second application of the compactness theorem shows that any theory that has arbitrarily large finite models, or a single infinite model, has models of arbitrary large [[cardinality]] (this is the [[Upward Löwenheim–Skolem theorem]]). So for instance, there are nonstandard models of [[Peano arithmetic]] with uncountably many 'natural numbers'. To achieve this, let <math>T</math> be the initial theory and let <math>\kappa</math> be any [[cardinal number]]. Add to the language of <math>T</math> one constant symbol for every element of <math>\kappa.</math> Then add to <math>T</math> a collection of sentences that say that the objects denoted by any two distinct constant symbols from the new collection are distinct (this is a collection of <math>\kappa^2</math> sentences). Since every {{em|finite}} subset of this new theory is satisfiable by a sufficiently large finite model of <math>T,</math> or by any infinite model, the entire extended theory is satisfiable. But any model of the extended theory has cardinality at least <math>\kappa</math>. ===Non-standard analysis=== A third application of the compactness theorem is the construction of [[Non-standard analysis|nonstandard models]] of the real numbers, that is, consistent extensions of the theory of the real numbers that contain "infinitesimal" numbers. To see this, let <math>\Sigma</math> be a first-order axiomatization of the theory of the real numbers. Consider the theory obtained by adding a new constant symbol <math>\varepsilon</math> to the language and adjoining to <math>\Sigma</math> the axiom <math>\varepsilon > 0</math> and the axioms <math>\varepsilon < \tfrac{1}{n}</math> for all positive integers <math>n.</math> Clearly, the standard real numbers <math>\R</math> are a model for every finite subset of these axioms, because the real numbers satisfy everything in <math>\Sigma</math> and, by suitable choice of <math>\varepsilon,</math> can be made to satisfy any finite subset of the axioms about <math>\varepsilon.</math> By the compactness theorem, there is a model <math>{}^* \R</math> that satisfies <math>\Sigma</math> and also contains an infinitesimal element <math>\varepsilon.</math> A similar argument, this time adjoining the axioms <math>\omega > 0, \; \omega > 1, \ldots,</math> etc., shows that the existence of numbers with infinitely large magnitudes cannot be ruled out by any axiomatization <math>\Sigma</math> of the reals.{{sfn|Goldblatt|1998|pages=[https://archive.org/details/lecturesonhyperr00gold_574/page/n12 10]–11}} It can be shown that the [[hyperreal number]]s <math>{}^* \R</math> satisfy the [[transfer principle]]:{{sfn|Goldblatt|1998|p=11}} a first-order sentence is true of <math>\R</math> if and only if it is true of <math>{}^* \R.</math>
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Compactness theorem
(section)
Add topic