Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Axiom schema of replacement
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
== Applications == The axiom schema of replacement is not necessary for the proofs of most theorems of ordinary mathematics. Indeed, [[Zermelo set theory]] (Z) already can interpret [[second-order arithmetic]] and much of [[type theory]] in finite types, which in turn are sufficient to formalize the bulk of mathematics. Although the axiom schema of replacement is a standard axiom in set theory today, it is often omitted from systems of [[type theory]] and foundation systems in [[topos]] theory. At any rate, the axiom schema drastically increases the strength of ZF, both in terms of the theorems it can prove - for example the sets shown to exist - and also in terms of its [[proof-theoretic]] consistency strength, compared to Z. Some important examples follow: * Using the modern definition due to [[John von Neumann|von Neumann]], proving the existence of any [[limit ordinal]] greater than ω requires the replacement axiom. The [[ordinal number]] ω·2 = ω + ω is the first such ordinal. The [[axiom of infinity]] asserts the existence of an infinite set ω = {0, 1, 2, ...}. One may hope to define ω·2 as the union of the sequence {ω, ω + 1, ω + 2,...}. However, arbitrary such [[class (set theory)|class]]es of ordinals need not be sets - for example, the class of all ordinals is not a set. Replacement now allows one to replace each finite number ''n'' in ω with the corresponding ω + ''n'', and thus guarantees that this class is a set. As a clarification, note that one can easily construct a [[well-ordered set]] that is isomorphic to ω·2 without resorting to replacement – simply take the [[disjoint union]] of two copies of ω, with the second copy greater than the first – but that this is not an ordinal since it is not totally ordered by inclusion. * Larger ordinals rely on replacement less directly. For example, ω<sub>1</sub>, the [[first uncountable ordinal]], can be constructed as follows – the set of countable well orders exists as a subset of <math>P({\mathbb N}\times {\mathbb N})</math> by [[axiom of separation|separation]] and [[axiom of power set|powerset]] (a [[binary relation|relation]] on ''A'' is a subset of <math>A\times A</math>, and so an element of the [[power set]] <math>P(A\times A)</math>. A set of relations is thus a subset of <math>P(A\times A)</math>). Replace each well-ordered set with its ordinal. This is the set of countable ordinals ω<sub>1</sub>, which can itself be shown to be uncountable. The construction uses replacement twice; once to ensure an ordinal assignment for each well ordered set and again to replace well ordered sets by their ordinals. This is a special case of the result of [[Hartogs number]], and the general case can be proved similarly. * In light of the above, the existence of an assignment of an ordinal to every well-ordered set requires replacement as well. Similarly the [[von Neumann cardinal assignment]] which assigns a [[cardinal number]] to each set requires replacement, as well as [[axiom of choice]]. * For sets of tuples recursively defined as <math>A^n=A^{n-1}\times A</math> and for large <math>A</math>, the set <math>\{A^n\mid n\in {\mathbb N}\}</math> has too high of a rank for its existence to be provable from set theory with just the axiom of power set, choice and without replacement. * Similarly, [[Harvey Friedman (mathematician)|Harvey Friedman]] showed that at least some instances of replacement are required to show that [[Borel set|Borel games]] are [[determinacy|determined]]. The proven result is [[Donald A. Martin]]'s [[Borel determinacy theorem]]. A later, more careful analysis by Martin of the result showed that it only requires replacement for functions with domain an arbitrary countable [[ordinal number|ordinal]]. * ZF with replacement proves the [[consistency]] of Z, as the set V<sub>ω·2</sub> is a [[model (logic)|model]] of Z whose existence can be proved in ZF. The [[cardinal number]] <math>\aleph_\omega</math> is the first one which can be shown to exist in ZF but not in Z. For clarification, note that [[Gödel's second incompleteness theorem]] shows that each of these theories contains a sentence, "expressing" the theory's own consistency, that is unprovable in that theory, if that theory is consistent - this result is often loosely expressed as the claim that neither of these theories can prove its own consistency, if it is consistent.
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Axiom schema of replacement
(section)
Add topic