Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Cardinality
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Cardinal numbers== {{main|Cardinal number}}In the above section, "cardinality" of a set was defined relationally. In other words, it was not defined as a specific object itself. However, such an object can be defined as follows. === Finite sets === {{main|Finite set}} [[File:Bijection.svg|thumb|200x200px|A [[bijective function]], ''f'': ''X'' → ''Y'', from set ''X'' to set ''Y'' demonstrates that the sets have the same cardinality, in this case equal to the cardinal number 4.]]Given a basic sense of [[natural numbers]], a set is said to have cardinality <math>n</math> if it can be put in one-to-one correspondence with the set <math>\{1,\,2,\, \dots, \, n\}.</math> For example, the set <math>S = \{ A,B,C,D \} </math> has a natural correspondence with the set <math>\{1,2,3,4\},</math> and therefore is said to have cardinality 4. Other terminologies include "Its cardinality is 4" or "Its cardinal number is 4". While this definition uses a basic sense of natural numbers, it may be that cardinality is used to define the natural numbers, in which case, a simple construction of objects satisfying the [[Peano axioms]] can be used as a substitute. Most commonly, the [[Von Neumann ordinal]]s. Showing that such a correspondence exists is not always trivial, which is the subject matter of [[combinatorics]]. ==== Uniqueness ==== An intuitive property of finite sets is that, for example, if a set has cardinality 4, then it does not also have cardinality 5. Intuitively meaning that a set cannot have both exaclty 4 elements and exactly 5 elements. However, it is not so obviously proven. The following proof is adapted from ''Analysis I'' by [[Terence Tao]].{{Sfn|Tao|2022|p=59}} [[File:Lemma function.png|thumb|Intuitive depiction of the function <math>g</math> in the lemma, for the case <math>|X| = 7.</math>]] Lemma: If a set <math>X</math> has cardinality <math>n \geq 1,</math> and <math>x_0 \in X,</math> then the set <math>X - \{x_0\} </math> (i.e. <math>X</math> with the element <math>x_0</math> removed) has cardinality <math>n-1.</math> Proof: Given <math>X</math> as above, since <math>X</math> has cardinality <math>n,</math> there is a bijection <math>f</math> from <math>X</math> to <math>\{1,\,2,\, \dots, \, n\}.</math> Then, since <math>x_0 \in X,</math> there must be some number <math>f(x_0)</math> in <math>\{1,\,2,\, \dots, \, n\}.</math> We need to find a bijection from <math>X - \{x_0\} </math> to <math>\{1, \dots n-1\}</math> (which may be empty). Define a function <math>g</math> such that <math>g(x) = f(x)</math> if <math>f(x) < f(x_0),</math> and <math>g(x) = f(x)-1</math> if <math>f(x) > f(x_0).</math> Then <math>g</math> is a bijection from <math>X - \{x_0\} </math> to <math>\{1, \dots n-1\}.</math> Theorem: If a set <math>X</math> has cardinality <math>n,</math> then it cannot have any other cardinality. That is, <math>X</math> cannot also have cardinality <math>m \neq n.</math> Proof: If <math>X</math> is empty (has cardinality 0), then there cannot exist a bijection from <math>X</math> to any nonempty set <math>Y,</math> since nothing mapped to <math>y_0 \in Y.</math> Assume, by [[Mathematical induction|induction]] that the result has been proven up to some cardinality <math>n.</math> If <math>X,</math> has cardinality <math>n+1,</math> assume it also has cardinality <math>m.</math> We want to show that <math>m = n+1.</math> By the lemma above, <math>X - \{x_0\} </math> must have cardinality <math>n</math> and <math>m-1.</math> Since, by induction, cardinality is unique for sets with cardinality <math>n,</math> it must be that <math>m-1 = n,</math> and thus <math>m = n+1.</math> === Aleph numbers === {{Main|Aleph number}} [[File:Aleph0.svg|right|thumb|169x169px|[[Aleph-nought]], aleph-zero, or aleph-null: the smallest infinite cardinal number, and the cardinal number of the set of natural numbers. ]] The [[aleph numbers]] are a sequence of cardinal numbers that denote the size of [[infinite sets]], denoted with an [[aleph]] <math>\aleph,</math> the first letter of the [[Hebrew alphabet]]. The first aleph number is <math>\aleph_0,</math> called "aleph-nought", "aleph-zero", or "aleph-null", which represents the cardinality of the set of all [[natural numbers]]: <math>\aleph_0 = |\N| = |\{0,1,2,3,\cdots\}| .</math> Then, <math>\aleph_1</math> represents the next largest cardinality. The most common way this is formalized in set theory is through [[Von Neumann ordinal]]s, known as [[Von Neumann cardinal assignment]]. [[Ordinal number]]s generalize the notion of ''order'' to infinite sets. For example, 2 comes after 1, denoted <math>1 < 2,</math> and 3 comes after both, denote <math>1 < 2 < 3.</math> Then, one define a new number, <math>\omega,</math> which comes after every natural number, denoted <math>1 < 2 < 3 < \cdots < \omega.</math> Further <math>\omega < \omega+1 ,</math> and so on. More formally, these ordinal numbers can be defined as follows: <math>0 := \{\},</math> the [[empty set]], <math>1 := \{0\} ,</math> <math>2 := \{0,1\},</math> <math>3 := \{0,1,2\},</math> and so on. Then one can define <math>m < n \text{, if } \, m \in n,</math> for examlpe, <math>2 \in \{0,1,2\} = 3,</math> therefore <math>2 < 3.</math> Further, defining <math>\omega := \{0,1,2,3,\cdots\}</math> (a [[limit ordinal]]) gives <math>\omega</math> the desired property of being the smallest ordinal greater than all finite ordinal numbers. Since <math>\omega \sim \N</math> by the natural correspondence, one may define <math>\aleph_0</math> as the set of all finite ordinals. That is, <math>\aleph_0 := \omega.</math> Then, <math>\aleph_1</math> is the set of all countable ordinals (all ordinals <math>\kappa</math> with cardinality <math>|\kappa| \leq \aleph_0</math>), the [[first uncountable ordinal]]. Since a set cannot contain itself, <math>\aleph_1</math> must have a strictly larger cardinality: <math>\aleph_0 < \aleph_1.</math> Furthermore, <math>\aleph_2</math> is the set of all ordinals with cardinality <math>\aleph_1,</math> and so on. By the [[well-ordering theorem]], there cannot exist any set with cardinality between <math>\aleph_0</math> and <math>\aleph_1,</math> and every infinite set has some cardinality corresponding to some aleph <math>\aleph_\alpha,</math> for some ordinal <math>\alpha.</math> ===Cardinality of the continuum=== {{main|Cardinality of the continuum}} [[File:Number line.png|thumb|The [[number line]], containing all points in its continuum.]] The cardinality of the [[real number]]s is denoted by "<math>\mathfrak c</math>" (a lowercase [[fraktur (script)|fraktur script]] "c"), and is also referred to as the [[cardinality of the continuum]]. Cantor showed, using the [[Cantor's diagonal argument|diagonal argument]], that <math>{\mathfrak c} >\aleph_0.</math> We can show that <math>\mathfrak c = 2^{\aleph_0},</math> this also being the cardinality of the set of all subsets of the natural numbers. The [[continuum hypothesis]] says that <math>\aleph_1 = 2^{\aleph_0},</math> i.e. <math>2^{\aleph_0}</math> is the smallest cardinal number bigger than <math>\aleph_0,</math> i.e. there is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the integers and that of the real numbers. The continuum hypothesis is [[independence (mathematical logic)|independent]] of [[Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice|ZFC]], a standard axiomatization of set theory; that is, it is impossible to prove the continuum hypothesis or its negation from ZFC—provided that ZFC is consistent.<ref>{{Cite journal | first = Paul J. | last = Cohen | title = The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis | journal = Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America | volume = 50 | issue = 6 | date = December 15, 1963 | pages = 1143–1148 | doi = 10.1073/pnas.50.6.1143 | pmid = 16578557 | pmc = 221287 | jstor=71858 | bibcode = 1963PNAS...50.1143C | doi-access = free }}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal | first = Paul J. | last = Cohen | title = The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis, II | journal = Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America | volume = 51 | issue = 1 | date = January 15, 1964 | pages = 105–110 | doi = 10.1073/pnas.51.1.105 | pmid = 16591132 | pmc = 300611 | jstor=72252 | bibcode = 1964PNAS...51..105C | doi-access = free }}</ref><ref>{{Citation|first=R|last=Penrose|author-link=Roger Penrose|title=The Road to Reality: A Complete Guide to the Laws of the Universe|publisher=Vintage Books|year=2005|isbn=0-09-944068-7}}</ref> One of Cantor's most important results was that the [[cardinality of the continuum]] (<math>\mathfrak{c}</math>) is greater than that of the natural numbers (<math>\aleph_0</math>); that is, there are more real numbers '''R''' than natural numbers '''N'''. Namely, Cantor showed that <math>\mathfrak{c} = 2^{\aleph_0} = \beth_1</math> (see [[Beth number#Beth one|Beth one]]) satisfies: :<math>2^{\aleph_0} > \aleph_0</math> :(see [[Cantor's diagonal argument]] or [[Cantor's first uncountability proof]]). The [[continuum hypothesis]] states that there is no [[cardinal number]] between the cardinality of the reals and the cardinality of the natural numbers, that is, :<math>2^{\aleph_0} = \aleph_1</math> However, this hypothesis can neither be proved nor disproved within the widely accepted [[ZFC]] [[axiomatic set theory]], if ZFC is consistent. The first of these results is apparent by considering, for instance, the [[tangent function]], which provides a [[one-to-one correspondence]] between the [[Interval (mathematics)|interval]] (−{{sfrac|1|2}}π, {{sfrac|1|2}}π) and '''R'''. The second result was first demonstrated by Cantor in 1878, but it became more apparent in 1890, when [[Giuseppe Peano]] introduced the [[space-filling curve]]s, curved lines that twist and turn enough to fill the whole of any square, or cube, or [[hypercube]], or finite-dimensional space. These curves are not a direct proof that a line has the same number of points as a finite-dimensional space, but they can be used to obtain [[Space-filling curve#Proof that a square and its side contain the same number of points|such a proof]]. Cantor also showed that sets with cardinality strictly greater than <math>\mathfrak c</math> exist (see his [[Cantor's diagonal argument#General sets|generalized diagonal argument]] and [[Cantor's theorem|theorem]]). They include, for instance: :* the set of all subsets of '''R''', i.e., the [[power set]] of '''R''', written ''P''('''R''') or 2<sup>'''R'''</sup> :* the set '''R'''<sup>'''R'''</sup> of all functions from '''R''' to '''R''' Both have cardinality :<math>2^\mathfrak {c} = \beth_2 > \mathfrak c </math> :(see [[Beth number#Beth two|Beth two]]). The [[Cardinality of the continuum#Cardinal equalities|cardinal equalities]] <math>\mathfrak{c}^2 = \mathfrak{c},</math> <math>\mathfrak c^{\aleph_0} = \mathfrak c,</math> and <math>\mathfrak c ^{\mathfrak c} = 2^{\mathfrak c}</math> can be demonstrated using [[cardinal arithmetic]]: :<math>\mathfrak{c}^2 = \left(2^{\aleph_0}\right)^2 = 2^{2\cdot{\aleph_0}} = 2^{\aleph_0} = \mathfrak{c},</math> :<math>\mathfrak c^{\aleph_0} = \left(2^{\aleph_0}\right)^{\aleph_0} = 2^{{\aleph_0}\cdot{\aleph_0}} = 2^{\aleph_0} = \mathfrak{c},</math> :<math> \mathfrak c ^{\mathfrak c} = \left(2^{\aleph_0}\right)^{\mathfrak c} = 2^{\mathfrak c\cdot\aleph_0} = 2^{\mathfrak c}.</math>
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Cardinality
(section)
Add topic