Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Mind–body dualism
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==History== ===Ancient Greek philosophy=== [[Hermotimus of Clazomenae]] (fl. c. 6th century BCE) was a philosopher who first proposed the idea of mind being fundamental in the cause of change.<ref>Aristotle. ''The Metaphysics'' 984b20, trans. by Hugh Lawson-Tancred. London, 2004.</ref> He proposed that physical entities are static, while reason<ref>{{Cite book|title=The basic works of Aristotle|last=Aristotle|date=2001|publisher=Modern Library|others=McKeon, Richard (Richard Peter)|isbn=0375757996|location=New York|pages=696 (Metaphysics, Book 1, Chapter 3)|oclc=46634018}}</ref> causes the change. [[Sextus Empiricus]] places him with [[Hesiod]], [[Parmenides]], and [[Empedocles]], as belonging to the class of philosophers who held a dualistic theory of a material and an active principle being together the origin of the universe.<ref>Sextus Empiricus, ''adv. Math.'' ix., ''ad Phys.'' i. 7</ref> Similar ideas were expounded by [[Anaxagoras]]. In the dialogue ''[[Phaedo]]'', [[Plato]] formulated his famous [[Theory of forms]] as distinct and immaterial substances of which the objects and other phenomena that we perceive in the world are nothing more than mere shadows.<ref name="Plat" /> In the ''Phaedo'', Plato makes it clear that the Forms are the ''universalia ante res'', i.e. they are ideal universals, by which we are able to understand the world. In his [[allegory of the cave]], Plato likens the achievement of philosophical understanding to emerging into [[Metaphor of the Sun|the sunlight]] from a dark cave, where only vague shadows of what lies beyond that prison are cast dimly upon the wall. Plato's forms are non-physical and non-mental. They exist nowhere in time or space, but neither do they exist in the mind, nor in the [[pleroma]] of matter; rather, matter is said to "participate" in form (μεθεξις, ''[[methexis]]''). It remained unclear however, even to Aristotle, exactly what Plato intended by that. [[Aristotle]] argued at length against many aspects of Plato's forms, creating his own doctrine of [[hylomorphism]] wherein form and matter coexist. Ultimately however, Aristotle's aim was to perfect a theory of forms, rather than to reject it. Although Aristotle strongly rejected the independent existence Plato attributed to forms, his [[metaphysics]] do agree with Plato's ''[[A priori and a posteriori|a priori]]'' considerations quite often. For example, Aristotle argues that changeless, eternal substantial form is necessarily immaterial. Because matter provides a stable substratum for a change in form, matter always has the potential to change. Thus, if given an eternity in which to do so, it ''will'', necessarily, exercise that potential. Part of Aristotle's ''psychology'', the study of the soul, is his account of the ability of humans to reason and the ability of animals to perceive. In both cases, perfect copies of forms are acquired, either by direct impression of environmental forms, in the case of perception, or else by virtue of contemplation, understanding and recollection. He believed the mind can literally assume any form being contemplated or experienced, and it was unique in its ability to become a blank slate, having no essential form. As thoughts of earth are not heavy, any more than thoughts of fire are causally efficient, they provide an immaterial complement for the formless mind.<ref name="Ari2">Aristotle. [c. mid 4th century BC] 1907. ''[[On the Soul|On the Soul (De anima)]]'', edited by [[Robert Drew Hicks|R. D. Hicks]]. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1968. Books II-III, translated by D.W. Hamlyn, Clarendon Aristotle Series. Oxford: Oxford University Press.</ref> ===From Neoplatonism to scholasticism=== The philosophical school of [[Neoplatonism]], most active in Late Antiquity, claimed that the physical and the spiritual are both emanations of ''the One''. Neoplatonism exerted a considerable influence on Christianity, as did the philosophy of Aristotle via [[scholasticism]].<ref>Whittaker, 1901, ''The Neo-Platonists'', Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.</ref> In the scholastic tradition of [[Saint Thomas Aquinas]], a number of whose doctrines have been incorporated into Roman Catholic [[dogma]], the soul is the substantial form of a human being.<ref name="auto">{{Cite web|url=https://www.newadvent.org/summa/1075.htm|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120119083516/http://www.newadvent.org/summa/1075.htm|title=Summa Theologiae: Man who is composed of a spiritual and a corporeal substance: and in the first place, concerning what belongs to the essence of the soul (Prima Pars, Q. 75)|url-status=dead|archive-date=19 January 2012|website=www.newadvent.org}}</ref> Aquinas held the ''Quaestiones disputate de anima'', or 'Disputed questions on the soul', at the Roman ''studium provinciale'' of the [[Dominican Order]] at [[Santa Sabina]], the forerunner of the [[Pontifical University of Saint Thomas Aquinas|Pontifical University of Saint Thomas Aquinas, ''Angelicum'']] during the academic year 1265–1266.<ref>Torrell, op. cit., 162</ref> By 1268 Aquinas had written at least the first book of the ''Sententia Libri De anima'', Aquinas' commentary on Aristotle's ''[[On the Soul|De anima]]'', the translation of which from the Greek was completed by Aquinas' Dominican associate at [[Viterbo]], [[William of Moerbeke]] in 1267.<ref>Torrell, 161 ff.</ref> Like Aristotle, Aquinas held that the human being was a unified composite substance of two substantial principles: form and matter. The soul is the substantial form and so the first actuality of a material organic body with the potentiality for life.<ref>Aristotle, de Anima II. 1–2.</ref> While Aquinas defended the unity of human nature as a composite substance constituted by these two inextricable principles of form and matter, he also argued for the incorruptibility of the intellectual soul,<ref name="auto"/> in contrast to the corruptibility of the vegetative and sensitive animation of plants and animals.<ref name="auto"/> His argument for the subsistence and incorruptibility of the intellectual soul takes its point of departure from the metaphysical principle that operation follows upon being (''agiture sequitur esse''), i.e., the activity of a thing reveals the mode of being and existence it depends upon. Since the intellectual soul exercises its own ''per se'' intellectual operations without employing material faculties, i.e. intellectual operations are immaterial, the intellect itself and the intellectual soul, must likewise be immaterial and so incorruptible. Even though the intellectual soul of man is able to subsist upon the death of the human being, Aquinas does not hold that the human person is able to remain integrated at death. The separated intellectual soul is neither a man nor a human person. The intellectual soul ''by itself'' is ''not'' a human person (i.e., an individual ''supposit'' of a rational nature).<ref>Summa theologiae, I. 29.1; 75.4ad2; Disputed Questions on the Soul I.</ref> Hence, Aquinas held that "soul of St. Peter pray for us" would be more appropriate than "St. Peter pray for us", because all things connected with his person, including memories, ended with his corporeal life.<ref>[[Thomas Aquinas|Aquinas, Thomas]] ''Summa Theologica''. trans. Fathers of the English Dominican Province, 2d, rev. ed., 22 vols., London: Burns, Oates & Washbourne; reprinted in 5 vols., Westminster, MD: Christian Classics, 1981.</ref> The [[Catholic]] doctrine of the [[Universal resurrection|resurrection of the body]] does not subscribe that, sees body and soul as forming a whole and states that at the [[second coming]], the souls of the departed will be reunited with their bodies as a whole person (substance) and witness to the [[apocalypse]]. The thorough consistency between dogma and contemporary science was maintained here<ref>{{cite web |title = Apostles' Creed |work = Catechism of the Catholic Church |url = http://www.va/archive/catechism/p1s1c3a2.htm#credo |url-status = live |archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20070928055619/http://www.va/archive/catechism/p1s1c3a2.htm#credo |archive-date = 2007-09-28 }}</ref> in part from a serious attendance to the principle that there can be only one truth. Consistency with science, logic, philosophy, and faith remained a high priority for centuries, and a university doctorate in theology generally included the entire science curriculum as a prerequisite. This doctrine is not universally accepted by Christians today. Many believe that one's immortal soul goes directly to [[Heaven]] upon death of the body.<ref>[[John Shelby Spong|Spong, John Selby]]. 1994. ''Resurrection: Myth or Reality''. New York: HarperCollins Publishing. {{ISBN|0-06-067546-2}}.</ref> ===Descartes and his disciples=== In his ''[[Meditations on First Philosophy]]'', [[René Descartes]] embarked upon a quest in which he called all his previous beliefs into doubt, to find out what he could be certain of.<ref name="De" /> In so doing, he discovered that he could doubt whether he had a body (it could be that he was dreaming of it or that it was an illusion created by an evil demon), but he could not doubt whether he had a mind. This gave Descartes his first inkling that the mind and body were different things. The mind, according to Descartes, was a "thinking thing" ({{langx|la|[[res cogitans]]}}), and an immaterial [[Substance theory|substance]]. This "thing" was the essence of himself, that which doubts, believes, hopes, and thinks. The body, "the thing that exists" ({{langx|la|[[res extensa]]|label=none}}), regulates normal bodily functions (such as heart and liver). According to Descartes, animals only had a body and not a soul (which distinguishes humans from animals). The distinction between mind and body is argued in ''Meditation'' VI as follows: I have a clear and distinct idea of myself as a thinking, non-extended thing, and a clear and distinct idea of body as an extended and non-thinking thing. Whatever I can conceive clearly and distinctly, God can so create. The central claim of what is often called ''Cartesian dualism'', in honor of Descartes, is that the immaterial mind and the material body, while being ontologically distinct substances, causally interact. This is an idea that continues to feature prominently in many non-European philosophies. Mental events cause physical events, and vice versa. But this leads to a substantial problem for Cartesian dualism: How can an immaterial mind cause anything in a material body, and vice versa? This has often been called the "problem of interactionism." Descartes himself struggled to come up with a feasible answer to this problem. In his letter to [[Elisabeth of Bohemia, Princess Palatine]], he suggested that spirits interacted with the body through the [[pineal gland]], a small gland in the centre of the brain, between the two [[Cerebral hemispheres|hemispheres]].<ref name="De" /> The term ''Cartesian dualism'' is also often associated with this more specific notion of causal interaction through the pineal gland. However, this explanation was not satisfactory: ''how'' can an immaterial mind interact with the physical pineal gland? Because Descartes' was such a difficult theory to defend, some of his disciples, such as [[Arnold Geulincx]] and [[Nicolas Malebranche]], proposed a different explanation: That all mind–body interactions required the direct intervention of God. According to these philosophers, the appropriate states of mind and body were only the ''occasions'' for such intervention, not real causes. These [[occasionalism|occasionalists]] maintained the strong thesis that all causation was directly dependent on God, instead of holding that all causation was natural except for that between mind and body.<ref name="Malebranche">[[Tad Schmaltz|Schmaltz, Tad]]. [2002] 2017. "[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/malebranche/ Nicolas Malebranche]." ''The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', edited by [[Edward N. Zalta|E. N. Zalta]].</ref> ===Recent=== In addition to already discussed theories of dualism (particularly the Christian and Cartesian models) there are new theories in the defense of dualism. [[Naturalistic dualism]] comes from Australian philosopher, [[David Chalmers]] (born 1966) who argues there is an explanatory gap between objective and subjective experience that cannot be bridged by reductionism because consciousness is, at least, logically autonomous of the physical properties upon which it supervenes. According to Chalmers, a naturalistic account of property dualism requires a new fundamental category of properties described by new laws of [[supervenience]]; the challenge being analogous to that of understanding electricity based on the mechanistic and Newtonian models of materialism prior to [[Maxwell's equations]]. A similar defense comes from Australian philosopher [[Frank Cameron Jackson|Frank Jackson]] (born 1943) who revived the theory of [[epiphenomenalism]] which argues that mental states do not play a role in physical states. Jackson argues that there are two kinds of dualism: # ''substance dualism'' that assumes there is second, non-corporeal form of reality. In this form, body and soul are two different substances. # ''property dualism'' that says that body and soul are different ''properties'' of the same body. He claims that functions of the mind/soul are internal, very private experiences that are not accessible to observation by others, and therefore not accessible by science (at least not yet). We can know everything, for example, about a bat's facility for echolocation, but we will never know how the bat experiences that phenomenon. In 2018, ''The Blackwell Companion to Substance Dualism'' was published that contains arguments for and against Cartesian dualism, emergent dualism, Thomistic dualism, emergent individualism and nonreductive physicalism.<ref name="Oldhoff 2019">{{cite journal|author=Oldhoff, Martine C. L.|year=2019|title=Review of The Blackwell Companion to Substance Dualism|journal=Journal of Analytic Theology|url=https://jat-ojs-baylor.tdl.org/jat/index.php/jat/article/view/316/541|volume=7|issue=1|pages=753–758|doi=10.12978/jat.2019-7.1200-51141105|doi-access=free}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal|author=Prestes III, Flavio|year=2019|title=Review: The Blackwell Companion to Substance Dualism|journal=Andrews University Seminary Studies |url=https://digitalcommons.andrews.edu/auss/vol57/iss2/21/|volume=57|issue=2|pages=414–418}}</ref> Contributors include [[Charles Taliaferro]], Edward Feser, William Hasker, J. P. Moreland, Richard Swinburne, [[Lynne Rudder Baker]], John W. Cooper and Timothy O'Connor.<ref name="Oldhoff 2019"/>
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Mind–body dualism
(section)
Add topic