Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Metaphysics
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
== Methodology == Metaphysicians employ a variety of [[Philosophical methodology|methods]] to develop metaphysical theories and formulate arguments for and against them.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Loux|Crisp|2017|pp=xi, 2}} | {{harvnb|Koons|Pickavance|2015|pp=2β3}} }}</ref> Traditionally, ''[[A priori and a posteriori|a priori]]'' methods have been the dominant approach. They rely on rational [[intuition]] and abstract reasoning from general principles rather than sensory [[experience]]. ''A posteriori'' approaches, by contrast, ground metaphysical theories in [[empirical observation]]s and scientific theories.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Koons|Pickavance|2015|pp=2β3}} | {{harvnb|Mumford|2012|loc=Β§ 10. What Is Metaphysics?}} | {{harvnb|Tahko|2015|pp=151β152}} | {{harvnb|Jaksland|2023|pp=198β199}} }}</ref> Some metaphysicians incorporate perspectives from fields such as [[physics]], [[psychology]], [[linguistics]], and [[history]] into their inquiry.<ref>{{harvnb|Koons|Pickavance|2015|pp=2β3}}</ref> The two approaches are not mutually exclusive: it is possible to combine elements from both.<ref>{{harvnb|Tahko|2015|pp=151β152, 172β173}}</ref> The method a metaphysician chooses often depends on their understanding of the nature of metaphysics, for example, whether they see it as an inquiry into the mind-independent structure of reality, as [[Metaphysical realism|metaphysical realists]] claim, or the principles underlying thought and experience, as some [[Metaphysical anti-realism|metaphysical anti-realists]] contend.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Mumford|2012|loc=Β§ 10. What Is Metaphysics?}} | {{harvnb|Koons|Pickavance|2015|pp=2β3}} | {{harvnb|Effingham|Beebee|Goff|2010|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=BBKsAgAAQBAJ&pg=PA123 123]}} | {{harvnb|Khlentzos|2021|loc=Lead Section, Β§ 3. The Anti-Realist Challenges to Metaphysical Realism}} }}</ref> ''A priori'' approaches often rely on intuitions{{em dash}}non-inferential impressions about the correctness of specific claims or general principles.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Daly|2015|pp=[https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1057/9781137344557_1 11β12]|loc=Introduction and Historical Overview}} | {{harvnb|Duignan|2009}} | {{harvnb|Tahko|2015|pp=177β180}}}}</ref>{{efn|The term ''intuition'' has a variety of other meanings in philosophy. It can refer to a simple opinion, a disposition to belief, what seems to be the case, or a relation between the mind and abstract objects.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Pust|2019|loc=Β§ 1. The Nature of Intuitions}} | {{harvnb|Lacey|2005|p=[https://www.oxfordreference.com/display/10.1093/acref/9780199264797.001.0001/acref-9780199264797-e-1255 442]}} }}</ref> The concept plays a central role in the philosophy of [[Immanuel Kant]], who understands intuitions as conscious, objective representations closely associated with the sense of space and time.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Janiak|2022|loc=Β§ 2.2 Kant's Understanding of Representation}} | {{harvnb|Lacey|2005|p=[https://www.oxfordreference.com/display/10.1093/acref/9780199264797.001.0001/acref-9780199264797-e-1255 442]}} }}</ref>}} For example, arguments for the [[A-theory of time]], which states that time flows from the past through the present and into the future, often rely on pre-theoretical intuitions associated with the sense of the passage of time.<ref>{{harvnb|Tahko|2015|pp=188β190}}</ref> Some approaches use intuitions to establish a small set of [[self-evident]] fundamental principles, known as [[axiom]]s, and employ [[deductive reasoning]] to build complex metaphysical systems by drawing conclusions from these axioms.<ref>{{harvnb|Goldenbaum|loc=Lead Section, Β§ 1. The Geometrical Method}}</ref> Intuition-based approaches can be combined with [[thought experiments]], which help evoke and clarify intuitions by linking them to imagined situations. They use [[counterfactual thinking]] to assess the possible consequences of these situations.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Tahko|2015|pp=177β178}} | {{harvnb|Brown|Fehige|2019|loc=Lead Section}} | {{harvnb|Goffi|Roux|2011|pp=[https://philpapers.org/rec/GOFOTV 165, 168β169]}} | {{harvnb|Eder|Lawler|Van Riel|2020|pp=915β916}} }}</ref> For example, to explore the relation between matter and consciousness, some theorists compare humans to [[philosophical zombies]]{{em dash}}hypothetical creatures identical to humans but without [[Consciousness|conscious experience]].<ref>{{harvnb|Kirk|2023|loc=Lead Section, Β§ 2. Zombies and Physicalism}}</ref> A related method relies on commonly accepted beliefs instead of intuitions to formulate arguments and theories. The [[Common sense|common-sense]] approach is often used to criticize metaphysical theories that deviate significantly from how the average person thinks about an issue. For example, common-sense philosophers have argued that [[mereological nihilism]] is false since it implies that commonly accepted things, like tables, do not exist.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Lawson|2020|pp=185β186}} | {{harvnb|Jaksland|2023|pp=198β199}} }}</ref> [[Conceptual analysis]], a method particularly prominent in [[analytic philosophy]], aims to decompose metaphysical concepts into component parts to clarify their meaning and identify essential relations.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Jackson|1998|pp=28β30}} | {{harvnb|Eder|Lawler|Van Riel|2020|p=915}} | {{harvnb|Shaffer|2015|pp=[https://www.jstor.org/stable/26602327 555β556]}} | {{harvnb|Audi|2006|loc=[https://www.encyclopedia.com/philosophy-and-religion/philosophy/philosophy-terms-and-concepts/philosophy Β§ Philosophical Methods]}} }}</ref> In [[Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]], the method of [[eidetic variation]] is used to investigate essential structures underlying [[Phenomenon|phenomena]]. This method involves imagining an object and varying its features to determine which ones are essential and cannot be changed.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Drummond|2022|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=VQ9hEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA75 75]}} | {{harvnb|Lohmar|2010|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=rsqdCfBCL1MC&pg=PA83 83]}} }}</ref> The [[Transcendental arguments|transcendental]] method is a further approach and examines the metaphysical structure of reality by observing what entities there are and studying the [[Condition of possibility|conditions of possibility]] without which these entities could not exist.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|PihlstrΓΆm|2009|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=srGLpb7pWdkC&pg=PA60 60β61]}} | {{harvnb|Stern|Cheng|2023|loc=Lead Section}} }}</ref> Some approaches give less importance to ''a priori'' reasoning and view metaphysics as a practice continuous with the empirical sciences that generalizes their insights while making their underlying assumptions explicit. This approach is known as ''naturalized metaphysics'' and is closely associated with the work of [[Willard Van Orman Quine]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Ney|2014|pp=30β31}} | {{harvnb|Van Inwagen|Sullivan|Bernstein|2023|loc=Β§ 4. The Methodology of Metaphysics}} | {{harvnb|Jaksland|2023|pp=198β199}} }}</ref> He relies on the idea that true sentences from the sciences and other fields have [[ontological commitments]], that is, they imply that certain entities exist.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Ney|2014|pp=37β38, 40}} | {{harvnb|Van Inwagen|Sullivan|Bernstein|2023|loc=Β§ 4. The Methodology of Metaphysics}} }}</ref> For example, if the sentence "some electrons are bonded to protons" is true then it can be used to justify that electrons and protons exist.<ref>{{harvnb|Ney|2014|p=41}}</ref> Quine used this insight to argue that one can learn about metaphysics by closely analyzing{{efn|Quine's method of analysis relies on [[logic translation]] to [[first-order logic]] in order to express claims as precisely as possible while relying [[existential quantifier]]s to identify their ontological commitments.<ref>{{harvnb|Ney|2014|pp=40β41}}</ref>}} scientific claims to understand what kind of metaphysical picture of the world they presuppose.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Ney|2014|pp=40β43}} | {{harvnb|Van Inwagen|Sullivan|Bernstein|2023|loc=Β§ 4. The Methodology of Metaphysics}} }}</ref> In addition to methods of conducting metaphysical inquiry, there are various methodological principles used to decide between competing theories by comparing their theoretical virtues. [[Ockham's Razor]] is a well-known principle that gives preference to simple theories, in particular, those that assume that few entities exist. Other principles consider [[explanatory power]], theoretical usefulness, and proximity to established beliefs.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|McDaniel|2020|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=3tDaDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA217 217β221]}} | {{harvnb|Ney|2014|pp=48β49}} | {{harvnb|Mumford|2012|loc=Β§ 10. What Is Metaphysics?}} | {{harvnb|Van Inwagen|Sullivan|Bernstein|2023|loc=Β§ 4. The Methodology of Metaphysics}} | {{harvnb|Koons|Pickavance|2015|pp=2β3}} }}</ref>
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Metaphysics
(section)
Add topic