Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Parmenides
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
== ''On Nature'' == Since antiquity, it has been believed Parmenides wrote only one work,{{efn|Diogenes Laertius, I 16 (A 13).}} later titled ''On Nature''.,{{efn|Diogenes Laertius, VIII 55 (A 9) and Simplicius, ''De caelo'' 556, 25 (A 14)}} a didactic poem written in [[dactylic hexameter]]verse. The language in which it was written is archaic, the same format in which the epic was expressed, the [[Homeric Greek|Homeric dialect]] and . This form has several uses: it facilitates the [[mnemonics]] and recitation of the poem;<ref>''Parmènide. Fragments Poème, Èdition, translation and commentary by Magalí Anne'' (preceded by Parmènide. Énoncer le verbe être ). Paris, Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin (Bibliothèque des textes philosophiques) 2012, pp. 215. {{ISBN|978-2-711-62414-0}}.</ref> allows games of poetic form, such as [[chiastic structure]]<ref>"L'etre, la Pensee et les liens du discours. Structures et argumentation du fr. 8, 1-49 D-K de Parménide", Tanja Ruben, Metis, {{ISSN|0995-3310}}, no. 5, 2007, pp. 163-184</ref> and the ''Ritournelkomposition''. Approximately 160 verses remain today from an original total that was probably near 800.{{sfn|Palmer|2020}} The poem was originally divided into three parts: an introductory [[wikt:proem|proem]] that contains an allegorical narrative which explains the purpose of the work, a former section known as "The Way of Truth" (''[[aletheia]]'', ἀλήθεια), and a latter section known as "The Way of Appearance/Opinion" (''[[doxa]]'', δόξα). Despite the poem's fragmentary nature, the general plan of both the proem and the first part, "The Way of Truth", have been ascertained by modern scholars, thanks to large excerpts made by [[Sextus Empiricus]]{{efn|''[[Against the Mathematicians]]'' {{harv|DK 28B1}}}} and [[Simplicius of Cilicia]].{{efn|''Commentary on [[Aristotle]]'s Physics'' {{harv|DK 28B8}}}}{{sfn|Palmer|2020}} Unfortunately, the second part, "The Way of Opinion", which is supposed to have been much longer than the first, only survives in small fragments and prose paraphrases.{{sfn|Palmer|2020}} === Proem === The introductory proem describes the narrator's journey to receive a revelation from an unnamed goddess on the nature of reality.{{sfn|Curd|2004|loc=I.3}} It is composed from a rich symbology, which draws mainly from the epic tradition (both [[Homer]] and [[Hesiod]]), but also from [[Orphism (religion)|Orphic]] symbology and other legends, and narrates an experience of a mystical-religious nature,<ref name="Bow98">Bowra, «The Proem of Parmenides», p. 98.</ref>{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=24-27}}{{sfn|Jaeger|1947|p=99}}{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} to which scholars have drawn comparison to varius mythological figures, including Etalides ([[Pherecydes of Syros|Pherecydes]], fragment 8 DK), Aristeas,{{efn|[[Herodotus]], ''History'' IV, 13ff}} Hermothymus{{efn|[[Pliny the Elder|Pliny]], ''H. N.'' VII 174}} and [[Epimenides]].{{efn|frag. 1 DK}}{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=24-27}} The latter ran into the goddesses Truth and Justice while his body was sleeping, which is very close to the story of the proem.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=24-27}} The narrative of the poet's journey includes a variety of allegorical symbols, such as a speeding chariot with glowing axles, horses, the House of Night, Gates of the paths of Night and Day, and maidens who are "the daughters of the Sun"{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1983|p=243}} who escort the poet from the ordinary daytime world to a strange destination, outside our human paths.{{sfn|Furley|1973|pp=1–15}} The allegorical themes in the poem have attracted a variety of different interpretations, including comparisons to [[Homer]] and [[Hesiod]], and attempts to relate the journey towards either [[Divine illumination|illumination]] or darkness, but there is little scholarly consensus about any interpretation, and the surviving evidence from the poem itself, as well as any other literary use of allegory from the same time period, may be too sparse to ever determine any of the intended symbolism with certainty.{{sfn|Curd|2004|loc=I.3}} The remainder of the work is then presented as the spoken revelation of the goddess without any accompanying narrative.{{sfn|Curd|2004|loc=I.3}} [[File:Istanbul - Museo archeol. - Auriga greco - Arcaico, sec. VI aC, da Cizico - Foto G. Dall'Orto 28-5-2006.jpg|thumb|Greek Charioteer. Bas-relief from the last quarter of the [[6th century BC]], Istanbul Archaeological Museum.]] The proem, begins with the description of a trip in a two-wheeled chariot (v. 7), pulled by a pair of mares, described as πολύφραστοι (''polýphrastoi'', v. 4), "attentive" or "knowledgeable". The image recalls the divine steeds of [[Achilles]], sometimes even endowed with a voice.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=22,24}} [[Pindar]] also gives us a similar image of draft beasts "leading" along a "pure path" or "luminous"<ref>ἐν καθαρᾷ κελεύθῷ, ''en katharâ keleuthô'', ''Olímpica'' VI, vv. 22–26</ref>{{sfn|Fränkel|1955|p=158}} There are so many common elements between the compositions that Bowra considers that either Pindar's mimics Parmenides's—it is later, from [[468 BC]]—, or, what he considers more likely, that they have a common source from which they are both influenced.{{sfn|Bowra|1937|p=102}} Everything seems to suggest that the chariot is directed by superior powers, and we must rule out, as Jaeger says,{{sfn|Jaeger|p=98}} the platonizing interpretation of [[Sextus Empiricus]], inspired by the myth of the "winged chariot" narrated in the ''[[Phaedrus (dialogue)|Phaedrus]]'' (246 d 3 – 248 d), in which the chariot symbolizes the human soul. Surely the composition has a closer relationship with the myth of the death of [[Phaethon]], since both this and the charioteers of this Parmenidean chariot are children of the [[Helios|Sun]], and the path that is traveled is that of Night and Day (v. 11). It is the same "solar chariot."{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=24}} [[File:Sappho Painter lekythos Helios MET.jpg|thumbnail|right|[[Helios]] and the Night. [[Lekythos]] from [[black-figure pottery]] from [[4th century BC]] Depicts Helios, ascending in his [[chariot]], Night, receding to the left and [[Eos]] to the right.]] This path leads from the “dwelling of Night” to the light (vv. 9–10). In verse 11 it is said that the way is "of Night and Day." [[Hesiod]] had spoken of the «house of Night» in ''[[Theogony]]'',<ref>vv. 748ss</ref> house in which both Night and Day dwell, only that in an alternate way, for never does the mansion accommodate both at the same time. The ancient view of the alternation of Night and Day can be characterized as a transit performed by both along the same path, but in ever different positions. The path of Night and Day is, therefore, a unique path. Hesiod geographically locates the abode of Night at the center of the Earth, in the immediate vicinity of [[Tartarus]]. Instead, Parmenides situates his scene, according to the material of the opening of the gates (they are "ethereal," v. 13), in the sky, like the gates of [[Mount Olympus]], which [[Apollonius of Rhodes]] describes as ethereal and situated, of course, in the sky.<ref>Argonautica III, 159–160</ref> Following [[Sextus Empiricus]], some scholars have seen this as the experience of a transition from Night to Light means the transit of the ignorance to knowledge,{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=24-27}} while others dispute this, because the sage begins his journey in a flash of light, as is typical of one who "knows".{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} It is certain that the author's intention is to give his work the character of a divine revelation, since the content is placed in the mouth of the goddess, analogous to the epic muse. And it is a revelation not available to ordinary men.{{sfn|Jaeger|1947|p=97-101}}{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=24-27}} that represents the abandonment of the world of everyday experience, where night and day alternate, a world replaced by a path of transcendent knowledge.{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} Werner Jaeger understood this path as a way of salvation that Parmenides would have heard about in the mystery religions, a straight path that leads to knowledge.{{sfn|Jaeger|1947|p=97-101}} The path on which he is led is interrupted by an immense stone gate, whose guardian is Dike. The daughters of the [[Helios|Sun]] persuade her, and she opens the door for the chariot to pass through (vv. 11–21). As in [[Homer]], the gates of Olympus are guarded by the [[Horae]], daughters of [[Zeus]] and [[Themis]],<ref>''Iliad'' V, 749</ref> the gate of the Parmenidean poem is curated by Dike, one of them. The Heliades persuade, with soft words, to the goddess to run the bolt, and she finally opens the door. Access to the truth is not, however, the merit of the "man who knows", since he is dragged by superior forces, the mares and the Heliades, his passage through the formidable barrier described in the poem is allowed by Dike and his journey he has from the first been in favor with Themis. Transit is in accordance with law.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=24-27}} In Parmenides' poem, Dike is adjectiveized as πολύποινος (''polýpoinos'', "rich in punishments" or "avenger," v. 14). The expression Δίκη πολύποινος (''Dike polýpoinos'') is present in an Orphic poem (fr. 158 Kern). This, plus the fact that Dike possesses the keys "of alternate uses" or "of double use" (ἀμοιβἤ, ''amoibê'', v. 14), another possible ritual element, made one think of a close relationship between Parmenides and the [[Orphism (religion)|Orphic cults]], so abundant in southern Italy.<ref>Jaeger, ''The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers,'' p. 99.</ref> The turn εἰδότα φῶτα (''eidóta phōta'', "man who knows"), opposed to mortals and their ignorance, does no more than reinforce this link (see [[Orpheus]], fr. 233 Kern).<ref>Bowra, “The Proem of Parmenides”, pp. 100–100. 109-110.</ref> [[File:Mousai Helikon Staatliche Antikensammlungen Schoen80 n1.jpg|thumb|[[Muse]] playing the [[zither]]. [[Lekythos]] Atticus, Achilles Painter, [[440 BC]] – [[430 BC]] The rock on which she sits reads [[Mount Helicon|''Hēlikon'']], thus representing one of the muses who inspired the '' [[Theogony]]'' of [[Hesiod]].]] Once the chariot passes the threshold, the “knowing man” is received by a goddess—whose identity is not revealed—with a typical gesture of welcome. Her speech, beginning at line 24, is the content of the rest of the poem. The narrator is greeted by a goddess, whose speech, Most scholars agree in showing the very close relationship between this nameless goddess (θεά, ''theá'') and the [[Muse]]s of the epic: [[Homer]] invokes her with the same word in the first verse from the ''Iliad'': «Sing, goddess...»; the divinity is the one she sings about, by virtue of the fact that she knows "all things" (''Il.'' II, 485). The Muses of [[Hesiod]] even specify something similar to what the Parmenidean goddess said about true and apparent speech: «We know how to tell many lies with appearances of truth; and we know, when we want, to proclaim the truth» (''Thegony'', vv. 27ff).{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}}{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=25}} She tells him, in the first place, that he has not been sent by an evil destiny, but by law and justice (vv. 26-28). It is not, says the goddess, this fate that has led the protagonist along the route of Night and Day: the author seems to oppose here the fate of the "man who knows" and that of Phaethon, whose disastrous journey in the chariot of the Sol only ended with his death.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=24}} "Moira" belongs to the set of divinities related to divine justice, such as Themis and Dike, who are the ones that have allowed the transit of a mortal through the route of the Sun. Themis personifies customary law;<ref>Jaeger, ''Paideia'', p. 106.</ref><ref>Deichgräber, ''Parmenides' Auffahrt zur Göttin des Recht'', Wiesbadenm Akademie der Wissenschaften un der Literatur in Mainz.</ref> in the epic, it is the set of norms of social behavior , not formulated, but that no mortal can ignore. The good disposition shown by the goddesses associated with law means that the trip has been permitted or approved by the divinity.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=23}}<ref>Lamb, ''Being, one is'', p. 44.</ref> By virtue of this, he continues, it is necessary that he know all things, both "the unshakable heart of persuasive truth" and "the opinions of mortals", because, although in these "there is no true conviction", without yet they have enjoyed prestige (vv. 28–32). It is necessary for the narrator to also know the opinions of mortals (vv. 31–32) because what is a matter of opinion (τὰ δοκοῦντα, ''tà dokoûnta'') is all-encompassing, which means that opinions are all that mortals could know without considering the revelation of the Parmenidean goddess. They have necessarily enjoyed prestige and that is why they must be known. The passage is closely related to the end of Fragment 8, v. 60ss, where the goddess says that she expounds the probable discourse on the cosmic order so that no mortal opinion outweighs the receiver of the revelation.<ref>Cordero, ''Siendo se es'', pp. 45-51.</ref> === ''The Way of Truth'' === In the ''Way of Truth'', an estimated 90% of which has survived,{{sfn|Palmer|2020}} Parmenides distinguishes between the unity of nature and its variety, insisting in the ''Way of Truth'' upon the reality of its unity, which is therefore the object of knowledge, and upon the unreality of its variety, which is therefore the object, not of knowledge, but of opinion.<ref name="Cornford p. 100">Cornford, "Parmenides' two ways", p. 100</ref> ==== B2 ==== [[Proclus]] preserves, in his commentary on ''Timaeus'' I 345, 18–20, two lines of Parmenides's poem, which together with six lines transmitted by Simplicius, in his commentary on Aristotle's ''Physics'', 116, 28–32–117, 1, form fragment 2 (28 B 2). There the goddess speaks of two "paths of inquiry that there are for thinking (nous)". The first is named as follows: "which is, and also cannot be that it is not" (v. 3); the second: "which is not, and also, must not be" (v. 5). The first way is "of persuasion", which "accompanies the truth" (v. 4), while the second is "completely inscrutable" or "impracticable", since "what is not" cannot be known, nor expressed (vv. 6–8). ==== B3 ==== Fragment B3<ref>[[Plotinus]], ''Enneads'' V, 1, 8</ref> is just a part of dactylic verse:{{langx|grc|...τὸ γὰρ αὐτὸ νοεῖν ἐστίν τε καὶ εἴναι}}. Following the order of the words and the literal meaning of each word, it could be translated (and understood) as follows: "the same thing is to think and to be". [[Plotinus]], who cites the text, believes he finds in it support for his idea of the identification of being with thinking, a fundamental idea of [[Neoplatonism]]. However, some modern scholars{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=28,31}}<ref>Burnet, ''Early Greek Philosophy'', p. 173ss</ref> have interpreted it as closer to "the same is to be thought and to be" For Jaeger, the semantic value of νοεῖν is not identical to that used later by [[Plato]], who opposes it to sensible perception. Rather this is an "awareness" of an object in what it is. The νοεῖν is not really νοεῖν if it does not know the real.<ref>*Werner Jaeger, ''The theology of the first Greek philosophers''</ref> Guthrie adds that the action of the verb cannot suggest the image of something that does not exist. In Homer it has a similar meaning to "see" (''Il'' XV, 422), rather it is the act by which someone receives the full meaning of a situation (''Il'' III, 396), not through a process of reasoning, but a sudden illumination. Subsequently, νοῦς (''noûs'') is conceived as a faculty that cannot be subject to error, as [[Aristotle]] will later say in ''Posterior Analytics'', 100b5.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|pp=31-34}} ==== B6 ==== In fragment B6, nine verses preserved by Simplicius,<ref>''Physics'' (86, 27-28 and 117, 4-13)</ref> Parminides continues to speak of the ways of thought. The first three verses argue against the second way, presented in B 2, v. 5: Postulates that it is necessary to think and say that "what is" is, since it is possible that it is, while it is impossible for "nothing" to be. And this is the reason why the goddess removes the "man who knows" from the second way. Immediately, the goddess speaks of a third path that must be left aside: the one in which mortals wander, wandering since they are dragged by a wavering mind, which considers that being and not being are the same, and at the same time it is not the same. himself (vv. 4–9). It is the way of opinion, already presented in B 1, v. 30. Fragment 6 has been interpreted by some philologists as a reference to the thought of [[Heraclitus]]. There it speaks of the "two-faced" (δίκρανοι v. 5), those who believe that "being and not being is the same and not the same" (vv. 8–9). This appears to be a criticism of the Heraclitean doctrine of the unity of opposites.{{efn|DK 22B88}} Verse 9 "from all things there is a retrograde way" (πἄντων δὲ '''παλίντροπός''' ἐστι κέλευθος), seems to point directly to an idea present in a fragment of Heraclitus: (22 B 60): "the up way and below is one and the same»; and to the same letter of another fragment (22 B 51): "...harmony of that which turns back» ('''παλίντροπος''' ἁρμονίη).<ref>Diels and Kranz, ''Fragments der Vorsocratic'' I, p. 162, app. cr. Cf. Guthrie, ''Greek History and Philosophy,'' II, p. 39</ref> [[File:Lions-Gate-Mycenae.jpg|300px|thumbnail|Gate of Lions, [[Mycenae]]]] In the Fragment 2, Parmenides presents two{{efn|Which are two is indicated by the beginning of v. 3 and 5, μέν (''mén'') – δέ (''dé''), particles that introduce in Greek a disjunction and not an enumeration.}} paths of inquiry, δίζησις (''dizēsis'' , v. 2), mutually exclusive: one must be followed and the other is inscrutable. In fragment 6, however, a third path appears from which one must turn away (v. 4ff). The characterization of these paths has initiated a discussion about the amount of paths presented and on the nature of these. [[Werner Jaeger]] says that throughout the writing the meaning of «path» is that of «salvation path». That is why he compares this disjunction of the paths with those of the religious symbolism of later Pythagoreanism, which presented a straight path and a path of error, in the sense of morally good and bad paths. The choice of one of them is made by man as a moral agent. He also offers as background a passage from ''Works and Days'' (286ff) where [[Hesiod]] presents a flat path, that of wickedness, and a steep one, that of virtue. Either way, he accepts that there is in the poem a transfer from religious symbolism to intellectual processes. In this sense, compared to the two exclusionary paths of fragment 2 (he calls them that of "being" and that of "not being"), the third path of fragment 6 is not a different path, but rather an inadmissible combination of these two, followed by those who have not noticed their mutual exclusion.<ref>Jaeger, ''The Theology of the First Greek Philosophers, pp. 101–103''</ref> Raven points out that the third way is that of mortals, who wander "two-headed" (δίκρανοι, ''díkranoi''), because they combine opposites, as Simplicius had noted.{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} Schofield argues that this third way had not been shown in fr. 2, since there were coherent alternatives between which a researcher must decide, while this is a path that anyone who does not make this decision and does not use his critical faculties finds himself on (fr. 6, vv. 6 –7), following both contradictory paths at the same time.{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} For Guthrie there are effectively three ways, the second is discarded and the third, which arises from the use of the senses and habit, includes the belief that "things that are not are" and "that being and not being are the same and not the same” (fr. 6, v. 8). ==== B7 ==== Another fragment, B7<ref>B7:cited in part by [[Plato]], ''Sophist'' 242a (the first two lines), and in part by [[Sextus Empiricus]], in ''Adversus Mathematicos'', VII, 111 (the next five verses)</ref> the next seven verses follow this reflection and concludes it: there is no way to prove "what is what is not" (v. 1). For this reason, the goddess indicates that it is necessary to deviate from this path of inquiry, going even against custom, which leads to the "inattentive gaze" and the "rumbling ear and the tongue", that is, to the senses (vv. 2 -4). Instead, she recommends following her controversial argument with reason (vv. 5–6). Part of line 6, and what remains of line 7, connects the theme of the paths of inquiry with fragment A8: only the path discourse dealing with 'what is' remains. ==== B8.1-4: Signs about "What is" ==== In the longest surviving fragment, B8,<ref>Simplicius ''Physics'' 145, 1–28 and 146, 1–24</ref> the goddess(v. 1-4) describes a series of "signs" about "what is": “unbegotten and indestructible” (ἀγένητον καὶ ἀνώλεθρον, v. 5-21), “whole and unique” (οὔλοε μοέον, v. 22-25), “immovable” (ἀτρεμής, v. 26-33) and “perfect” (τελεῖον, v. 42-49), which are along the path and which come to be a set of attributes of "what is". The program itself, however, concludes with an inexplicable "endless (in time)" (ἠδ᾽ ἀτέλεστον) which would contradict verse 5, which indicates that "what is" is foreign to both the past and the future.<ref>Owen, "Eleatic questions," p. 101</ref> Owen offers the following conjecture as a solution to this difficulty: the reading is a copyist's error, seduced by the reiteration of negative prefixes in the poem (ἀγένητον... ἀνώλεθρον... ἀτρεμές) and by the influence of a Homeric cliché,.<ref>(''Il'' IV, 26)</ref> and should read ἠδὲ τελεῖον, "perfect." With this amendment a complete correspondence between the program and the arguments is achieved.<ref>Owen, "Eleatic Questions", p. 102</ref> Guthrie nevertheless decides on the original reading (the only one attested in the manuscripts) and rejects Owen's emendation, understanding this "infinity" in a new sense, different from the Homeric use of the term, which precisely means "incomplete", "unfinished" and that contradicts the ideas presented in the poem about the attributes of perfection of the entity.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=41}} Raven follows the reading of Diels,<ref>Kirk and Raven, ''The Presocratic Philosophers'' fr. 347, p. 382</ref> but Schofield follows Owen's conjecture.{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} ==== B8.5-21 "What is" cannot be begotten or destroyed ==== From verse 5 to 21 a lengthy argument is developed against generation and corruption. Verse 5 posits On the other hand, if nothing can be understood or said about "what is not", then there is no possibility of finding out from where it would have been generated, nor for what reason it would have been generated "before" or "after", emerging from nothing. (verses 6–10). It is necessary that it be completely, or that it not be at all, therefore it cannot be admitted that from what is not something arises that exists together with "what is" (vv. 11-12). Generation and corruption are prohibited by Justice, by virtue of a decision: "it is or it is not", and it has been decided to abandon this last path as inscrutable, and follow the first, the only true path (vv. 14-18) . Nor can the entity, being, be born. And if he was born, he is not. Nor can it be if it is going to be. Therefore the generation is extinct, and perishing cannot be known (vv. 19–21). The first sign that the goddess deals with is the one related to the entity's relationship with time, the generation and corruption. In verse 5 of fragment 8 she affirms that the entity was not in the past nor should it be in the future, but is entirely now (νῦν ἔστι ὁμοῦ πᾶν). The past and the future have no meaning for the entity, it ''is'' in a perpetual present, without temporal distinction of any kind.{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} What follows (vv. 6–11) is the argument against the birth or generation of what is. The first words (“one”, ἕν, and “continuous”, συνεχές) advance the content of another argument located later on unity and continuity (vv. 22–25). From there, she wonders what genesis would you look for? It denies the possibility that "what is" arises from "what is not", since one cannot think or say “what is not” (vv. 7–9) there would be no need for something "that is" to emerge from "what is not" (vv. 9-10). Schofield has interpreted Parmenides here as 'appealing to the [[principle of sufficient reason]]. He supposes that everything that comes to be must contain in itself a principle of development ("necessity", χρέος) sufficient to explain its generation. But if something does not exist, how can it contain such a principle?»{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} The meaning of lines 12–13 is ambiguous, due to the use of a [[pronoun]] (αὐτό) that can be interpreted as referring to the object that has been spoken of for nine lines, “what is”, or as referring to the subject of the sentence in which it appears: «what is not». The first alternative and the final meaning of the sentence would be: from "what is not" something cannot arise that becomes together with "what is", that is, something other than "what is". This sentence would have the same content as that of verse 36–37: "nothing can exist apart from what is." This interpretation has been followed by Raven,{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} but rejected by Guthrie, because it introduces, according to him, elements alien to the argument about generation and corruption that dominates the section as a whole. He interprets as follows: 'what is not' can only be generated from 'what is not'.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=41}} In this sense, it would be one of the first versions of the phrase ''[[ex nihilo nihil fit]]'', "from nothing nothing arises", which is also an axiom already accepted by the "philosophers of nature', as [[Aristotle]] observes (''Physics'' 187a34).{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=43}} Throughout the fragment there is no direct argument against corruption, but it can be deduced from postulating as exclusive the "is" and the "is not" (v. 16), and rejecting the "is not" (vv. 17– 18): perishing involves accepting that "what is" might "not be" in the future. Likewise, the generation implies that "what is" has not been in the past (vv. 19–20).{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} From the point of view of the history of thought, Parmenides achieves a true intellectual achievement by distinguishing here the ''enduring'' from the ''eternal''. What is ''enduring'' is in time: it is the same now as it was thousands of years ago, or in the future. This is how the ancients thought of the perdurability of the cosmos or physical universe, as distinct from the eternity of what it is (Plato, ''Timaeus'' 38c2, 37e–38a). While eternity was posited by the Ionians—[[Anaximander]] said that their ἄπειρον was immortal, eternal, and ageless—they had also thought that their respective principles were starting points of the world. Parmenides, on the other hand, shows that if it is accepted that what is is eternal, it must be one, and cannot be the beginning of a multiform world, of an order of plural elements. Much less of a world subject to becoming, as Aristotle also expresses as the opinion of the ancient philosophers: "what is does not become, because it already is, and nothing could come to be from what it is not" ('Physics' ' 191a30).{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=44}} ==== B8.22-25: "What is" is whole ==== From verse 22 to 25, the poem deals with the condition of integrity of "what is". No parts can be distinguished in it, since it is uniform: there is no more and less in it, it is simply full of "what is", and is alone with itself. In this passage Parmenides denies two ideas present in the cosmogonies and in the speculations of thinkers before him: the gradation of being and the [[emptiness]]. Anaximenes had spoken of the condensation and rarefaction of his principle (13 A 7), actions that, in addition to generating movement (which has already been rejected by Parmenides), supposes assuming certain degrees of density, but strictly adhering to "what is" prevents this type of gradual differences of existence.{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} In this cosmogony, for the cosmos to emerge from the beginning, it must have some unevenness of texture, lack of cohesion or balance.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=47}} It also prevents differentiating things according to their nature, as Heraclitus had intended (22 B 1). Guthrie rejects the reference to Anaximenes exposed above.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=46}} But above all he seems to reject here the idea of emptiness, which the [[Pythagoreans]] considered as necessary to separate the units, physical and arithmetical at the same time, from which the world was composed.{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}}{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=47}} Apart from these historical considerations, the passage has generated some controversy regarding the dimension that Parmenides mentioned when referring to continuity. Owen interpreted this continuity of being to refer exclusively to time,<ref>Owen, ''Eleatic questions'', p. 97</ref> but Guthrie understands that the beginning of the passage ("neither differentiable is...", οὐδε διαρετόν ἐστιν, v. 22) introduces a new and independent argument from the previous one, and that the predicate of the homogeneous ("is a uniform whole", πᾶν ἔστιν ὁμοῖον, same verse), even based on what is said in verse 11: "it must be completely, or not be at all", that is, in a part of the argument against the generation, has a further consequence: in the present continuous of "what is," he exists fully, and not in varying degrees.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=47}} Schofield indicates that Parmenides thinks of a continuity of what is, in whatever dimension he occupies, and this quote also refers to a temporal continuity.{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} ==== B8.26-33 "What is" is motionless ==== [[File:Odysseus Sirens BM E440 n2.jpg|thumb|200px|right|[[Odysseus]] and the sirens. Detail of an Attic [[stamnos]] of [[red-figure pottery|red-figure]] from [[Vulci]], 480–470 BCE, [[British Museum]]. Illustrates the passage from ''Odyssey''. XII where the hero is ''immobile'', constrained by the ''bonds'' that hold him to the mast of his ship.]] Immobility is treated from verses 26 to 33. This is understood first as a denial of transit, as generation and corruption, which have already been repelled by true conviction (vv. 26-28). Then he says that "what is" remains in its place, in itself and by itself, compelled by necessity, which holds it "with strong ties" (vv. 29-31). An additional reason for his immobility is that he lacks nothing (v. 32), since, lacking something, he would lack everything (v. 33). ==== B8.42-49: "What is" is perfect ==== [[File:Being Parmenides.png|thumb|Parmenides describes "what is" as a rounded ball, with its entire surface equidistant from the center.{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 28B8}}.42-49}}]] In verse 42,{{efn|''What are given as verses 34-41 in [[Diels-Kranz numbering]] have been displaced from the original position after verse 52 (See {{harvnb|Palmer|2020|loc=2.3}})''}} the discourse deals with the attribute of perfection: "what is" is similar to the mass of a well-rounded ball, it cannot be less somewhere and more somewhere else, all of it is equidistant from the center (vv. 43–44) Remaining identical to itself, it fulfills its own limits.(vv. 45–49). [[File: OdysseyNausikaa.png | thumb | 250px | Illustration of the game scene of Nausicaa and her handmaidens with a ball (σφαίρα), by [[John Flaxman]].]] Parmenides (v. 43) describes what is as a "σφαίρης" (sphaires), which in classical Greek means "that which has a spherical shape" which in antiquity led some commentators to claim that Parmenides believed in a "spherical universe"<ref>Hippolytus, ''Refutation of all heresies'', I, 11 , 2 = DK 28 A 23</ref> or a "spherical god"<ref>Aetius, DK 28 A 31.</ref> or even a statement about the roundness of the Earth.<ref>Theophrastus in Diog. VIII, 4 and Aetius, III, 15, 17 (for both citations, cf. DK 28 A 44).</ref> This interpretation has a parallel with the later geometrical model of the universe in Plato's ''Timaeus'', where the Demiurge makes the world spherical, because the sphere is that figure that contains all the others, the most perfect and similar to itself.<ref>Cornford, ''Plato and Parmenides'', p. 44.</ref> However, both Plato and Parmenides distinguished between the "sensible" world and the "intelligible" world, and, considering the world of the senses unreal, so it is unlikely either of them was intending to make a statement about the shape of the material universe.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|pp=39-40}}{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} Additionally, in the [[Homeric Greek|Homeric language]] used by Parmenides, ''σφαίρα'' is nothing more than a ball, like the one they played with [[Nausicaa]] and her female servants upon reaching them [[Odysseus]].<ref>''Od.'' VI, 100</ref><ref name="Owenp95">Owen, «Eleatic questions», p. 95</ref>{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=57}} The Parmenidean entity could be thought of as a sphere, but it is ultimately neither spherical nor spatial, taking into account that it is a reality not perceptible by the senses, it is timeless, it does not change its quality and it is immobile. The "boundaries" are not spatial, but a sign of invariance.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=59}} The limits are also not temporary, since this would involve accepting generation and corruption. The comparison with the sphere is required because it represents a reality in which every point is the same distance from the center, and therefore no point is more "true" than another. It is an image of the continuity and uniformity of the entity.<ref name="Owenp95" /><ref>Stokes, ''One and Many'', p. 140</ref> Already [[Plato]] had understood that the Eleatics denied movement because the One lacked a place where it could move;<ref>(''Theaetetus '' 180de)</ref> this idea of the absence of a void was first expressed by [[Melissus of Samos]].<ref>Kirk & Strokes, ''Phronesis'' V , 1960, p. 1–4</ref> In this attribute of what is, the idea of limit (πεῖρας) plays a fundamental role. It is associated with bonds or chains, such as those with which [[Odysseus]] was tied by his companions in ''Od.'' XII, 179. These uses maintain the idea of a certain deprivation of spatial mobility. The idea of limit is also related to "what is established by the gods." Because, in the poem, one of the arguments in favor of immobility is the fact that “what is” cannot be incomplete, this would be “illicit”: οὐκ ἀτελεύτητον τό ἐόν θἔμις εἶναι (v. 32). The term ἀτελεύτητον is used in ''Il.'', I, 527: there [[Zeus]] says that what he assents to «does not remain unfulfilled». This is equivalent to Parmenides' "is perfect" (τετελεσμένον ἔστι v. 42).{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=49}} The use of «limit» linked to the sense of «perfection» or «consummation» is also attested in ''Il''. XVIII, 501 and ''Od'' V, 289.<ref>Owen, ''Studies in Presocratic Philosophy'', II, p. 65</ref> The "limit" is, moreover, one of the fundamental principles of the [[Pythagoreans]], and heads the left column of their [[Table of Opposites]] (58 B 4–5 = ''Met''. 986a23), column in which were also, among others, the One, the Still and the Good.{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} === ''The Way of Opinion'' === In the significantly longer, but far worse preserved latter section of the poem, ''Way of Opinion'', Parmenides propounds a theory of the world of apperance and its development, pointing out, however, that, in accordance with the principles already laid down, these cosmological speculations do not pretend to anything more than mere appearance. The structure of the cosmos is a fundamental binary principle that governs the manifestations of all the particulars: "the Aether fire of flame" (B 8.56), which is gentle, mild, soft, thin and clear, and self-identical, and the other is "ignorant night", body thick and heavy.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p= 61–62}}{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 28B8}}, lines 53–54.}} [[Cosmology]] originally comprised the greater part of his poem, explaining the world's origins and operations.{{efn|[[Stobaeus]], i. 22. 1a}} Some idea of the [[Spherical Earth|sphericity of the Earth]] also seems to have been known to Parmenides.{{sfn|Palmer|2020}}{{efn|DK 28B10}} ==== B8.50-52, 34-41: The Fates ==== The end of fragment 8, preserved by Simplicius, corresponds to an initial characterization of the opinion pathway. The goddess indicates that with the above considerations trustworthy speech ends, and a "deceitful order of words" begins: that of the opinions of mortals (vv. 50-52). The content of lines 34 to 36{{efn|''What are given as verses 34-41 in [[Diels-Kranz numbering]] have been displaced from the original position after verse 52 (See {{harvnb|Palmer|2020|loc=2.3}})}} is deeply related to fragment B3: it postulates that what must be intellectively known is that by which intellection is: intellective knowing itself (''noein'') is revealed in "what is"; in fact, there is nothing more than "what is" Lines 34 to 36 and the first half of 37 are linked to the verse that constitutes fragment 3 and its meaning. And this is revealed by the parallelism of the construction νοεῖν ἔστιν (fr. 3) / ἔστιν νοεῖν (fr.8, v. 34). The [[Moirai]] keeps the entity whole and motionless (vv. 37–38); This forces us to think that everything that mortals have thought to be true is nothing more than a network of mere names that designate changes: to be born and to perish, to be and not to be, to vary in place and color (vv. 39–41). Guthrie notes that, in this passage, Parmenides elevates his diction to epic and religious solemnity, and gives an important role to the divinities Moiras and Ananke. The use of the word refers to the scene of [[Hector]] who, chained to his Destiny, has ''remained'' outside the walls of [[Troy]] ('' Il ''. XXII, 1– 6). Guthrie understands that Parmenides' reason for holding the idea of immobility is that "what is" is continuous and indistinguishable in parts, which prevents it from moving as a whole or changing internally.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=50}} The first line is interpretable in multiple ways.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=53}} First of all, the interpretation depends on the determination of the [[Subject (grammar)|subject]]. Thus, Guthrie, following [[Eduard Zeller|Zeller]], [[Hermann Fränkel|Fränkel]] and [[Walther Kranz|Kranz]], understands that νοῆμα is linked to the verb ἔστι, so that the subject would be «what what can be thought. The meaning of the first line would be: "What can be thought and the thought that 'is' are the same."{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=53}} On the other hand, [[Hermann Diels|Diels]], Von Fritz and [[Gregory Vlastos|Vlastos]], among others, have thought that the subject is the [[Infinitive|infinitive Mood]] νοεῖν: that is “thinking”. Diels and Von Fritz,<ref>''Von Fritz, «Classical Philology» 1945, p. 238''</ref> following the interpretation of Simplicius, they have also understood that οὐνεκέν has a causal or consecutive value (Guthrie gives it the value of a mere [[Conjunction (grammar)|conjunction]]), so the meaning of this verse would be: "Thinking is the same as that which is the cause of thinking." Ultimately, there are two possible interpretations: 1) the one that maintains that what is said here is that thinking and being have a relationship of identity.<ref name="Vlastos53">Vlastos, «Jean Zafiropoulo: L'école éléate». ''Gnomon'' 1953, p. 168</ref> 2) that the idea of fragment 3 is being repeated here. and that of verse 2 of fragment 2: That is, that thought only reveals itself and realizes itself in "what is".{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=45}} Vlastos argues that the thought he knows can hardly be denied existence. But if it exists, it must be part of what it is. But what is has no parts, but is homogeneous. Then thinking can only be the totality of what it is. What it is is intelligence.<ref name="Vlastos53" /> In this dispute, [[Francis Macdonald Cornford|Cornford]] rightly points out that nowhere in the poem does Parmenides indicate that his One thinks, and that no Greek of his day would have held that 'if A exists, A thinks'. Rather he held that thought cannot exist without something existing.<ref>Cornford, '' Plato and Parmenides '', p.34, n. 1</ref> Owen points out that Plato, in ''Sophist'' 248d–249a, hinted that Parmenides was not faced with the problem of whether the real possesses life, soul, and understanding.<ref>Owen, ''Eleatic Questions» , p. 95, no. 5''</ref> The only sure thing is that there is a close relationship between what is and knowing, which are faced by the actions of being born and perishing, being and not being, changing place or color, which strictly speaking "are mere names" which mortals have agreed to assign to things that are unreal, and then persuaded themselves of their reality. The whole of these names is the content of the way of opinion.{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}}{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=55}} ==== B8.53-64: Primordial Elements ==== [[File:Olympians.jpg|thumb|The cosmology of Parmenides gave a [[theogony]], a story of the origin of the gods.]] In fragment 8, the elements that make up the opposition to which the world of appearance can be reduced have been presented: φλογός αἰθέριον πῦρ (''phlogós aitherion pŷr'', «ethereal fire of the flame», v. 56) and νύξ (''nýx'', «night», v. 59). Mortals have distinguished two forms, πῦρ (''pŷr'', "fire", v. 56) and νῦξ (''nŷx'', "night", v. 59). In relation to these opposites, the goddess says that "the mortals have erred", however line 54, which contains the reason for the error, presents three possibilities of translation. She literally says τῶν μίαν οὐ χρεών ἐστιv. These three interpretations exhaust the possibilities of the text, and all have been supported by specialists. These, the mortals, have given names to two forms, with which they have gone astray, because it is only lawful to name one (v. 54). They assigned these forms different properties, and considered them opposite: on the one hand, fire, soft, light and homogeneous; on the other, the night, compact and heavy (vv. 55–59). The goddess declares this speech no longer true, but plausible in appearance, and communicates it so that, in the order of opinions, the sage is not surpassed either (vv. 60-61). [[Simplicius of Cilicia|Simplicius]], pointed out that in this passage Parmenides transits from the objects of reason to sensible objects.<ref>''Commentary on Physics'' 30, 14</ref> The goddess calls the content of this second part βροτῶν δόξας (''brotôn dóxas'', "opinions of mortals", v. 51). Keep in mind that δόξα means ''what seems real'' or is presented to the senses; ''what seems true'' constituting the beliefs of all men; and ''what seems right'' to man.<ref name="Cornford p. 100"/> The speech does not pretend to be "true", since everything that could be said reliably has already been said. On the contrary, what he will present will be a κόσμος ἀπατηλός (''kósmos apatēlós'', «deceitful order»), since he presents beliefs as if they were presided over by an order.{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} # The first interpretation consists in indicating that the error is to name the two forms, since only one must be named. ##[[Aristotle]] understood that, once Parmenides considered that outside of what is nothing there is, he was forced to take phenomena into account, and to explain them he postulated opposites: cold and hot, or fire and earth , and that hot is «what is» and cold «what is not» (''Met'' I 5, 986b30 = A 24). ## [[Eduard Zeller|Zeller]] translated the passage as "one of which should not be named". This means that the other exists and can be named.<ref>Zeller, ''Die Philosophie der Griechen'', p. 701.</ref> ## Burnet followed this interpretation, adding that these forms can be identified with the Pythagorean principles of limit and limitlessness.{{sfn|Burnet|1892|p=186}} ## Schofield reflects this interpretation by translating the passage "of which they must not necessarily name more than one".{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} # In contrast to this, another interpretation indicates that none of the forms should be named. # The most accepted interpretation indicates that the error is not to consider these two forms at the same time, but to name only one. ##Simplicius, who transmits the quote, thought that the error consists in not naming both contraries in the description of the physical world. The sentence would then say "of which it is not proper to name a single one." Modern philology has followed this interpretation in some of its exponents, such as Coxon and [[John Raven]]. ## The first indicates that Parmenides knows that starting from a single form necessarily leads to uniformity, since only one element can originate itself. He begins in two ways, deliberately, in order to explain not only the multiplicity, but the contradiction in the world.<ref>Coxon, «The Philosophy of Parmenides», p. 142.</ref> [[Hermann Fränkel|Fränkel]], even deciding on an intertextual interpretation that corresponds to the first exposed here: «only one should be named», does so without this implying that one of the two forms is more real than the other. The Light must not be identified with the first way. Men name two forms, light and night, and this is the mistake, since one should be named, "what is".<ref>Fränkel, ''Wege und Formen des frühgriechischen Denkens'', p. 180</ref> Guthrie, who makes a critical compilation of all the positions on the matter, does not find Cornford and Diels' objection to Zeller's translation convincing, since Parmenides' expression is irregular. Cornford's translation would also be better represented by the textual presence of a οὐδὲ μίαν (''udé mían'', «none») and that of Simplicius and Raven by a μίαν μόνην (''mían mónēn'', «only one» ).{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=64}} Guthrie argues that Parmenides thinks that it is illogical to accept, on the one hand, that the world contains a plurality of things, and on the other, that this plurality can arise from a single principle.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=68}} The passage from the way of truth to the deceptive words of mortal opinions is a real problem for specialists. Even when the goddess tells the "man who knows" that she reveals this order to him as plausible, so that no mortal can outdo him (vv. 60–61), this reason has been interpreted in various ways. In antiquity, [[Aristotle]] conceived the first part of the poem as the consideration of the One κατὰ τὸν λόγον (''katá tón lógon'', «regarding the concept»<ref>García Yebra, ''Metaphysics of Aristotle'', p.41</ref> or "as to definition" or "as to reason"<ref>Guthrie, ''History of Greek Philosophy'', II, p. 70, n. 67</ref>), and the second as the consideration of the world according to the senses (''Met'' 986b31 = A 24). [[Theophrastus]] followed him at this point,<ref>Theophrastus in [[Alexander of Aphrodisias]], ''in Met.'' A 3, 984b3 (A7).</ref> and Simplicius adds that, although the goddess calls the speech of the second part "conjectural" and "misleading", she does not consider it completely false (''Physics'' 39, 10–12 = A 34). [[Werner Jaeger|Jaeger]], following Reinhardt,{{sfn|Reinhardt|p=90}} he thought that Parmenides was presented with the need to explain the origin of the deceptive appearance. And he had no other means than to narrate the origin of the world constituted by appearances, that is, to compose a cosmogony.<ref>Jaeger, ''The Theology of the First Greek Philosophers'', p. 106</ref> Owen argues that the content of the second part is merely a dialectical device, and does not imply an ontological claim.<ref>Owen, «Eleatic Questions», p. 85</ref> ==== B9: Day and Night ==== Fragment 9 mentions again what was described in the final part of Fragment 8 as what mortals have conceived as the dual foundation of the world of appearance: the opposing principles "light" and "night", and says that everything is full of these opposites, and that nothing belongs exclusively to one of the two. In Fragment 9, Parmenides goes a step further, and states that the entire sensible realm can be reduced to manifestations of this pair of opposites, night and light ({{langx|grs|φάος}}, v.1), and that both penetrate the whole of reality equally.{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} These forms can be considered to head a list of opposites, which serve as qualities to sensible things.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=72}} The idea of grouping under the fundamental opposite pair all the attributes of it has its parallel in the [[table of opposites]] of [[Pythagoras]].<ref>(58 B 4–5 = ''Met''. 986a23)</ref> Of course, in the Parmenidean table, oppositions that are not sensible must be excluded.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=90}} For Simplicius,<ref>''Physics'' 38, 18–28</ref> it was clear that assigning fire the attribute of agent, which [[Alexander of Aphrodisias]] had done,<ref>''Commentary on Aristotle's Meteorology'', 31, 7 = A 7</ref> was a mistake. The reliability of all such evidence dependent on Aristotle is now highly doubted,<ref>Cherniss, ''Aristotle's Criticism of Presocratic Philosophy, 1935, p. 48, no. 192.''</ref> even when they reflect previous cosmogonic beliefs and it is not too risky to consider fire as active and earth as passive.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=72}} The fact that the goddess indicates (v.3-4) that everything is full of both night and light "equally" (ἴσων ἀμφοτέρων, ''ísōn amphotérōn'') is ambiguous; it could either mean "of equal rank," which would agree with Aristotle's interpretation, according to which one form "is" and the other "is not,"<ref>(''Met. 986b31'')</ref>{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}}<ref>Fränkel, ''Wege und Formen Frühgriechischen Denkens'', pp. 180–181.</ref><ref>Coxon, The Philosophy of Parmenides, p. 141</ref> or it could refer to an equality in quantity or extension, which would parallel a Pythagorean expression<ref>quoted by Diogenes Laertius, in ''Lives'' VIII, 26</ref> where in the cosmos, light and darkness are posited to equally cover (ἰσόμοιρα) the earth.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=72}} ==== B10-15: Cosmology ==== [[File:Milky_Way_Night_Sky_Black_Rock_Desert_Nevada.jpg|thumb|The milky way features in Parmenides' cosmology]] Although the second half of the poem is less well preserved, a rough outline of Parmenides' cosmology can still be tentatively reconstructed on the basis of the surviving fragments along with testimony of his philosophical theories from ancient doxographers, especially [[Aetius (philosopher)|Aetius]] and [[Plutarch]]. [[Plutarch]] says in ''adv. Colotem'' 1114b (A10) that, from the original opposites, Parmenides elaborates an order in which the [[Earth]], the [[heaven]], the [[Sun]], the [[Moon]], the origin of man, and that he "did not fail to discuss any of the important questions." Simplicius,<ref>in ''de Caelo'' 559, 26 (A11)</ref> says that Parmenides also dealt with the parts of animals. Plato places him alongside [[Hesiod]] as the creator of a [[theogony]],<ref>(''Symposium'' 195c)</ref> and Cicero<ref>(''de Natura Deorum'' I, 11, 28 = A37)</ref> reports that the poem contained certain Hesiodic abstract divinities,<ref>(''Theogony'' 223– 232)</ref> such as Love, War and Discord.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=74}} Fragments 10 and 11, which are introductory to cosmology, confirm what is expressed by the testimonies, at least with regard to the Sun, the Moon, and the sky, although it also includes the [[Aether (classical element)|aether]], the stars, the constellations (n.b.: the word σήματα used by Parmenides can mean both "constellations" and "signs"){{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} and the Milky Way, and mythical elements such as [[Mount Olympus]]. The Parmenidean goddess presents a cosmic order in fr. B12<ref>Simplicius in his ''Physics'', 39, 14 and 31, 13</ref> and the summary of Aetius<ref>II, 7, 1 = fr. A 37</ref> that is extremely difficult to reconstruct, due to the scarcity and obscurity of the fragments.{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}}{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=76}}{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} The beginning of fragment 12 and the testimony of Aetius <ref>(II, 7, 1 = A37)</ref> introduce into cosmology certain "rings"<ref>(στεφάναι ''stephánai'', which should be translated by «rings» and not by «crowns», as does [[Cicero]], ''De nat. deor.'' I 11, 28 = A37</ref>) The existence of concentric rings of a diverse nature is postulated as the structure of the cosmos: some rings were of pure fire and others of a mixture of fire and darkness, the rings closer to the center participated more in fire, while those further from the center were more filled with night. There are also rarified and dense ones. Surrounding everything is a solid wall. The doctrine of the rings seems to be the influence of [[Anaximander]]<ref>(12 A 11 and Aetius, II, 20, 1; 21, 1 and 16, 5)</ref> and of [[Hesiod]],<ref>''Theogony'' 382</ref> who speaks of the "crowned" sky and the stars. At the center of the system, an unnamed [[daimon]]<ref>(δαίμων "dáimōn", "goddess" or "demon")</ref> coordinates all the cosmological elements, both sensible opposites and Necessity, and presides over the mixture and attraction of the sexes, and the "abhorrent" birth.<ref>(B 12, 3-6)</ref> [[Plutarch]]<ref>('' Amat. '' 756e–f)</ref> calls her [[Aphrodite]], before citing fragment 13 of her, which marks her as the mother of [[Eros]], while Aetius identifies her with Ananke and also Dike, Δίκη, present in the proem, here presiding over movement and birth. [[File:Ananka i Mojre.JPG|thumb|Modern illustration of Ananke, the personification of Necessity, above the Moirai, the Fates in the [[Myth of Er]] of Plato's ''Republic'']] Fragment 10 gives a predominant role to [[Ananke]](Ἀνάγκη, ''Anánkē''), the personification of Necessity, which obliges Heaven to keep the stars within its limits (πεῖρατα).{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} The role of Necessity in this system has been compared to the one Plato gives it in the [[Myth of Er]].<ref>''Republic'' 616b–621d</ref> There Plato places it in the center of certain concentrically arranged turrets, each one representing the celestial spheres that support the fixed stars, the nearby heavenly bodies, the planets, the Moon and the Sun.<ref>Morrison, «Parmenides and Er», in: ''[[The Journal of Hellenic Studies]]'' 75 (1955).</ref>{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=76-77}}{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} Both this cosmology and the Myth of Er also have similarities with Pythagorean cosmology, where the center of the universe was generally identified with [[Hestia]] (in non-geocentric Pythagorean systems such as [[Philolaus]]) and with Mother Earth (in geocentric Pythagorean systems).{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=77}} Diogenes Laertius claims that to Parmenides was the first to state idea that the Earth has a spherical shape and that it is located in the center,<ref>(''Lives'', IX 21)</ref> but he also cites testimonies that affirm that it was [[Pythagoras]] and not Parmenides who held these ideas<ref>(''Lives'', VIII, 48)</ref> and also that it was [[Anaximander]].<ref>(''Lives'' II, 1)</ref> Beyond the evident doubts that these contradictory affirmations generate, Guthrie believes that in this Parmenides followed Pythagoras in the general lines of the description of the physical world.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=79}} Various reconstructions of the concentric annular strata and their identification with the substantial elements of the cosmos have been attempted: * The solid wall that surrounds everything is sometimes identified with the [[Aether (mythology)|ether]],<ref name="MorrC">Morrison, «Parmenides and Er», p. 64.</ref><ref name="UntC">Untersteiner, ''Parmenide'', p. 83.</ref> or as distinct from all other elements.<ref name="FC">Finkelberg, «The Cosmology of Parmenides», p. 313ff.</ref> * The ethereal ring of pure fire is where the morning star is located.<ref name="FC"/> * Rings of mixed nature. The upper ring of these is the sky proper where the Sun is, and a little lower down, the stars, the Milky Way and, closer to the dense rings, the Moon.<ref name="UntC"/><ref name="FC"/> * The dense rings, whose substance is night, are usually identified with the Earth.<ref name="UntC"/><ref name="MorrC"/><ref name="FC"/> Fragments 14 and 15 refer to the [[Moon]]: alien light (ἀλλότριον φώς) shining around the Earth» and always looking at the Sun, which has been interpreted as the observation that the Moon reflects the rays of the Sun.{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} Aetius attributes this view Parmenides,<ref>(II, 26, 2 = A 42)</ref> but claims that Thales had already said it, and later Parmenides and [[Pythagoras]] added to this,<ref>(II, 28, 5 = A42)</ref> On the other hand, [[Plato]] attributes the idea to [[Anaxagoras]], and elsewhere Aetius says that Parmenides thought that the Moon was made of fire (A 43) —implying that he thought he had his own light.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=80}} In the Homeric poems,<ref>(''Il''. V, 214; ''Od''. XVIII, 219)</ref> "alien light" simply means "foreigner", without reference to light.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=80}} In fragment 15a there is only one word: ὑδατόριζον:(''hydatórizon'', “rooted in water”) an adjective referring, according to its transmitter ([[Basil of Caesarea]]), to [[Earth]]. This idea has been compared to the Homeric tradition that conceived of [[Ocean (mythology)|Ocean]] as the origin of all things,<ref>(''Iliad'' XIV, 246)</ref><ref>Sapphiropulus, ''L'Ecole eleate'', p. 124.</ref> as a more general allusion to the Homeric world, which located various rivers in [[Hades]],<ref>(v. ''Od.'' X, 513)</ref>{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=79}} to the roots of the Earth mentioned by [[Hesiod]]<ref>(''Theogony'', 728)</ref> and [[Xenophanes]],<ref>(21 A 41)</ref> or to [[Thales of Miletus]]'s view that the Earth floated on water.<ref>Joge Pérez Tudela, ''Poema'', pp. 216-217.</ref> ==== B16: Sense perception ==== Parmenides also provided a theory of knowledge through sense perception, a description of which is preserved by [[Theophrastus]]. Theophrastus, in recording Parmenides' opinion on sensation,{{efn|''de Sensu 3'', DK 28A46}} indicates that Parmenides holds that sense perception proceeds by resemblance between what feels and the thing felt. He reports Parmenides as saying that everything is composed of two elements, hot and cold, and their intelligence depends on this mixture, present in the limbs of humans. In fact, the nature of each limb or organ, what is preponderant in them, is what is perceived. That is why corpses, which have been abandoned by fire, light and heat, can only perceive the opposite, cold and silence. Everything that exists, he concludes, contains some knowledge. Just as [[Empedocles]] later said that "we see earth with earth, water with water" ,{{efn|31 B 109}} he held, in accordance with his doctrine of sensible opposites, that mortal perception depends on the admixture of these opposites in the different parts of the body (μέλεα). But, following his teacher's interpretation of the Parmenidean opposites, he says that the thought that arises from the hot is purer. Fränkel therefore thought that this theory of knowledge was valid not only for sensory perception, but also for the thought of "what is".<ref>Fränkel, ''Wege und Formen Frühgriechischen Denkens, pp. 170 and 174.''</ref> Vlastos maintains that the identity of the subject and the object of thought is valid both for the knowledge of what is (B3) and for sensible knowledge, although he accepts that «what is" is "everything identical" (B8, v. 22), while the structure of the body is a mixture of different elements,<ref>Vlastos, "Parmenides' Theory of Knowledge", p. 68.</ref> and that the preponderance of light does not physically justify the knowledge of "what is". The way to conceive a pure knowledge is not by imagining a situation in which the body has more light, but that it is made of pure light, and this is what Parmenides does in the journey recounted in the proem.<ref>Vlastos, « Parmenides' Theory of Knowledge”, pp. 71–73.</ref> Other commentators disagree with transposing this "physical" explanation to the plane of the path of truth. Guthrie{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=83}} and Schofield{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} emphasize the exclusive belonging of this theory to the field of the sensible, of mortal opinion. ==== B17-18: Embryology ==== Parmenides cosmology also included medical theories: two testimonies<ref>(Aetius, [[Censorinus]] and [[Lactantius]] in A 53 and A 54)</ref> indicate that Parmenides was interested in [[embryology]], and two fragments, preserved by [[Galen]] (B17), and [[Caelius Aurelianus]] (B18) are from medical contexts. Parmenides' theory of embryology claims that each of the sexes is conceived on a different side in the mother's womb:{{efn|on the right boys, on the left girls{{harv|DK 28B17}}}} the sex of the embryo depends, on the one hand, on the side from which it is conceived in the womb, and on the other, on the side from which the father's seed comes. But the character and traits of the begotten being depend on the mixture of masculine and feminine potencies (B18). So that: # If the semen comes from the right side and lodges in the right side of the womb, the embryo will be a well-built and masculine man. # If the semen comes from the left side and lodges in the left side of the womb, the result is a female with feminine features. # When the semen comes from the left, and lodges to the right of the uterus, it gives rise to a man, but with feminine traits such as outstanding beauty, whiteness, small stature, etc. # If the semen originates on the right and descends to the left of the uterus, this time it forms a woman, but with markedly masculine traits: virility, excessive height, etc.<ref name="Poema226">Jorge Pérez Tudela, '' Poem'', p. 226.</ref> This medical theory exhibits similarities to the medical doctrine of [[Alcmaeon of Croton]],<ref>(DK24 B4)</ref> which conceived a "equal distribution" (ἰσονομία) of forces between man and woman in determining the child's sex,{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} and contrasts with the later theory of [[Anaxagoras]], to whom Aristotle<ref>''[[Generation of animals|de Generatione animalium]]'', IV, I 763b 30</ref> attributes the theory that only male seed determines sex.<ref name="Poema226" /> Parmenides' association of boys with "the right" and girls with "the left" in Fragment B17, combined with the testimony of Aristotle (A52) and Aetius (A53) attribute to Parmenides the view that the masculine is associated with the cold and the dense,<ref>(Aetius V, 7, 1–7 = A53)</ref> and the feminine with the hot and diffuse,<ref>Aristotle, ''De part. an.'' 648a25 = A 52</ref> upsets the general Greek conception, which associates right with light and warm, and left with dark and cold,{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=90}} but resembles a Pythagorean [[Table of opposites]], leading some scholars{{efn|Burnet|1892|p=185}} to postulate that Parmenides probably carried out an outline of Pythagorean cosmology. However, on the other hand, many of the other opposites in the Pythagorean table are never mentioned by Parmenides, there are elements completely unrelated to Pythagoreanism, such as the "rings" in fragment 12, and no ancient commentators claimed to find any traces of Pythagorean doctrine in his poem, instead the Way of Opinion is unanimously considered to be Parmenides' own invention.{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|p=391}} Another possibility is that, unlike in cosmology, Parmenides did not see masculine and feminine as pure opposites in embryology, where observation and empirical guidance allowed for a greater variety of opinions on the role of males.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=90}} ==== B19: Conclusion ==== Fragment B19,<ref>Simplicius, ''de Caelo'', 558, 8-10</ref> located at the conclusion of the Way of Opinion, reaffirms the concepts expressed before<ref>fr. B 8, vv. 50-61)</ref> that the cosmos belongs to the Way of Opinion (v. 1), that the things with in the cosmos come to be and pass away (v. 1 and 2), and that these things are predicated on names assigned by mortals (v. 3).<ref>Jorge Pérez Tudela, ''Poema, pp. 231-232.''</ref> === Dating, style and transmission === In the introduction to the poem,{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 28B1}}.24}} the goddess speaks to the recipient of the message, presumably Parmenides himself, calling him κοῦρε (''koûre'', "young man"). It has been suggested that because this word refers to a man no older than thirty years and, taking into account Parmenides' date of birth, we can place the creation of the poem between [[490 BC]] and the [[475 BC]]<ref name="Corn1" />{{sfn|Kirk|Raven|Schofield|1982}} But it has been objected that the word must be understood in its religious context: it indicates the relation of superiority of the goddess with respect to the man who receives the revelation from her.<ref>Burkert, «Das Proëmium», p. 14, no. 32;</ref> Guthrie supports this idea, supporting it with a quote ([[Aristophanes]], ''[[The Birds (play)|The Birds]]'' 977) where the word precisely indicates not the age of a man (which otherwise he is not young), but rather his situation with respect to the interpreter of oracles by whom he is being questioned. His conclusion is that it is impossible to say at what age Parmenides wrote the poem.{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=16}} Much has been said about the poetic form of his writing. [[Plutarch]] considered it to be just a way of avoiding prose,{{efn|Plutarch, ''Quomodo adol. poet. aud. deb.'' 16c (A 15).}} and criticized its versification.{{efn|Plutarch, ''De aud.'' 45a–b (A 16).}} Proclus said that despite using metaphors and tropes, forced by the poetic form, his writing is more like prose than poetry.{{efn|Proclus, ''Parmenides'' I p. 665, 17 (A 18).}} Simplicius, to whom we owe the preservation of most of the text that has come down to us, holds a similar opinion: one should not be surprised at the appearance of mythical motifs in his writing, due to the poetic form he uses.{{efn|Simplicius, ''Physics'', 144, 25 – 147, 2 (A 20).}} For [[Werner Jaeger]], Parmenides' choice of the didactic epic poem form is a highly significant innovation. It involves, on the one hand, the rejection of the prose form introduced by [[Anaximander]]. On the other hand, it means a link with the form of the ''Theogony'' of [[Hesiod]]. But the link affects not only the form, but also certain elements of the content: in the second part of Parmenides' poem (fragments B 12 and 13) Hesiod's cosmogonic [[Eros]] appears (''Theogony'' 120) along with a large number of allegorical deities such as War, Discord, Desire,{{efn|[[Cicero]], ''de deor. nat.'', I, 11, 18 (A 37).}} whose origin in the ''Theogony'' cannot be doubted. However, putting these cosmogonic elements in the second part, dedicated to the world of appearance, also involves the rejection of this way of understanding the world, a way alien to the Truth for Parmenides. Hesiod had presented his theogonic poem as a revelation from divine beings. He had made the invocation of the muses —already an epic convention— the story of a personal experience of initiation into a unique mission, that of revealing the origin of the gods. Parmenides in his poem presents his thought on the One and Immobile Entity as a divine revelation, as if to defeat Hesiod at his own game.<ref>Jaeger, ''The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers'' , p. 95s.</ref> Parmenides's poem, as a complete work, is considered irretrievably lost. From its composition, it was copied many times, but the last reference to the complete work is made by Simplicius, in the 6th century: he writes that it had already become rare by then ('Physics' ', 144).<ref>Cordero, ''Being, one is'', p. 26.</ref> What comes to us from the poem are fragmentary quotes, present in the works of various authors. In this Parmenides does not differ from the majority of the [[Pre-Socratic philosophers]]. The first one who cites it is Plato, then Aristotle, Plutarch, Sextus Empiricus and Simplicius, among others. Sometimes the same group of verses is cited by several of these authors, and although the text of the citations often coincide, other times they present differences. This gives rise to arguments and speculations about which quote is the most faithful to the original. There are also cases in which the citation is unique.<ref>Cordero, ''Siendo, se es'', p. 27.</ref> The reconstruction of the text, starting from the reunion of all existing citations, began in the [[Renaissance]] and culminated in the work of [[Hermann Diels]], ''Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker'', in 1903, which established the texts of most of the philosophers prior to Plato.<ref>Cordero, ''Siendo, se es'', p. 28.</ref> This work contains a total of 19 presumably original "fragments" of Parmenides, of which 18 are in [[Ancient Greek|Greek]] and one consists of a rhythmic translation in [[Latin]]. 160 verses of the poem have been preserved. According to Diels' estimates, these lines represent about nine-tenths of the first part (the "way of truth"), plus one-tenth of the second (the "way of opinion").{{sfn|Guthrie|1979|p=18}} Diels' work was republished and modified by [[Walther Kranz]] in 1934. The edition had such an influence on studies that today Parmenides (as well as the other pre-Socratics) is cited according to the order of the authors and fragments of it. Parmenides occupies chapter 28 there, so he is usually cited with the abbreviation DK 28, then adding the type of fragment (A = ancient commentaries on life and doctrine; B = the fragments of the original poem) and finally the number. snippet (for example, "DK 28 B 1"). Even though this edition is considered canonical by philologists, numerous reissues have appeared that have proposed a new order of the fragments, and some specialists, such as Allan Hartley Coxon, have made collations on the manuscripts in which some of the quotations are preserved, and have questioned the reliability of the reading and establishment of Diels's text.<ref>Tudela, ''Poema'',Introduction, p. 7.</ref>
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Parmenides
(section)
Add topic