Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Forcing (mathematics)
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
== Cohen forcing == The simplest nontrivial forcing poset is <math> (\operatorname{Fin}(\omega,2),\supseteq,0) </math>, the finite partial functions from <math> \omega </math> to <math> 2 ~ \stackrel{\text{df}}{=} ~ \{ 0,1 \} </math> under ''reverse'' inclusion. That is, a condition <math> p </math> is essentially two disjoint finite subsets <math> {p^{-1}}[1] </math> and <math> {p^{-1}}[0] </math> of <math> \omega </math>, to be thought of as the "yes" and "no" parts of {{nowrap|<math> p </math>,}} with no information provided on values outside the domain of <math> p </math>. "<math> q </math> is stronger than <math> p </math>" means that <math> q \supseteq p </math>, in other words, the "yes" and "no" parts of <math> q </math> are supersets of the "yes" and "no" parts of <math> p </math>, and in that sense, provide more information. Let <math> G </math> be a generic filter for this poset. If <math> p </math> and <math> q </math> are both in <math> G </math>, then <math> p \cup q </math> is a condition because <math> G </math> is a filter. This means that <math> g = \bigcup G </math> is a well-defined partial function from <math> \omega </math> to <math> 2 </math> because any two conditions in <math> G </math> agree on their common domain. In fact, <math> g </math> is a total function. Given <math> n \in \omega </math>, let <math> D_{n} = \{ p \mid p(n) ~ \text{is defined} \} </math>. Then <math> D_{n} </math> is dense. (Given any <math> p </math>, if <math> n </math> is not in <math> p </math>'s domain, adjoin a value for <math> n </math>—the result is in <math> D_{n} </math>.) A condition <math> p \in G \cap D_{n} </math> has <math> n </math> in its domain, and since <math> p \subseteq g </math>, we find that <math> g(n) </math> is defined. Let <math> X = {g^{-1}}[1] </math>, the set of all "yes" members of the generic conditions. It is possible to give a name for <math> X </math> directly. Let :<math> \underline{X} = \left \{ \left (\check{n},p \right ) \mid p(n) = 1 \right \}.</math> Then <math>\operatorname{val}(\underline{X},G) = X.</math> Now suppose that <math> A \subseteq \omega </math> in <math> V </math>. We claim that <math> X \neq A </math>. Let :<math> D_{A} = \{ p \mid (\exists n)(n \in \operatorname{Dom}(p) \land (p(n) = 1 \iff n \notin A)) \}.</math> Then <math>D_A</math> is dense. (Given any <math> p </math>, find <math> n </math> that is not in its domain, and adjoin a value for <math> n </math> contrary to the status of "<math> n \in A </math>".) Then any <math> p \in G \cap D_A</math> witnesses <math> X \neq A </math>. To summarize, <math> X </math> is a "new" subset of <math> \omega </math>, necessarily infinite. Replacing <math> \omega </math> with <math> \omega \times \omega_{2} </math>, that is, consider instead finite partial functions whose inputs are of the form <math> (n,\alpha) </math>, with <math> n < \omega </math> and <math> \alpha < \omega_{2} </math>, and whose outputs are <math> 0 </math> or <math> 1 </math>, one gets <math> \omega_{2} </math> new subsets of <math> \omega </math>. They are all distinct, by a density argument: Given <math> \alpha < \beta < \omega_{2} </math>, let :<math> D_{\alpha,\beta} = \{ p \mid (\exists n)(p(n,\alpha) \neq p(n,\beta)) \},</math> then each <math> D_{\alpha,\beta} </math> is dense, and a generic condition in it proves that the αth new set disagrees somewhere with the <math> \beta </math>th new set. This is not yet the falsification of the continuum hypothesis. One must prove that no new maps have been introduced which map <math> \omega </math> onto <math> \omega_{1} </math>, or <math> \omega_{1} </math> onto <math> \omega_{2} </math>. For example, if one considers instead <math> \operatorname{Fin}(\omega,\omega_{1}) </math>, finite partial functions from <math> \omega </math> to <math> \omega_{1} </math>, the [[first uncountable ordinal]], one gets in <math> V[G] </math> a bijection from <math> \omega </math> to <math> \omega_{1} </math>. In other words, <math> \omega_{1} </math> has ''collapsed'', and in the forcing extension, is a countable ordinal. The last step in showing the independence of the continuum hypothesis, then, is to show that Cohen forcing does not collapse cardinals. For this, a sufficient combinatorial property is that all of the [[antichain]]s of the forcing poset are countable.
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Forcing (mathematics)
(section)
Add topic