Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Perfect competition
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
==Criticisms== The use of the assumption of perfect competition as the foundation of [[price theory]] for product markets is often criticized as representing all agents as passive, thus removing the active attempts to increase one's welfare or profits by price [[undercutting]], [[product design]], advertising, innovation, activities that β the critics argue<!-- who? --> β characterize most industries and markets. These criticisms point to the frequent lack of realism of the assumptions of [[product homogeneity]] and impossibility to differentiate it, but apart from this, the accusation of passivity appears correct only for short-period or very-short-period analyses, in long-period analyses the inability of price to diverge from the natural or long-period price is due to active reactions of entry or exit. Some economists have a different kind of criticism concerning perfect competition model. They are not criticizing the [[price taker]] assumption because it makes economic agents too "passive", but because it then raises the question of who sets the prices. Indeed, if everyone is price taker, there is the need for a benevolent planner who gives and sets the prices, in other word, there is a need for a "price maker". Therefore, it makes the perfect competition model appropriate not to describe a decentralized "market" economy but a centralized one. This in turn means that such kind of model has more to do with [[communism]] than capitalism.<ref>This was the kind of criticism made by the [http://www.autisme-economie.org "autisme economie" movement] Example of this kind of criticisms: http://www.paecon.net/PAEtexts/Guerrien1.htm</ref> Another frequent criticism is that it is often not true that in the short run differences between [[supply and demand]] cause changes in price; especially in manufacturing, the more common behaviour is alteration of production without nearly any alteration of price.<ref>Lee (1998)</ref> The critics of the assumption of perfect competition in product markets seldom question the basic [[neoclassical economics|neoclassical]] view of the working of market economies for this reason. The [[Austrian School]] insists strongly on this criticism, and yet the neoclassical view of the working of market economies as fundamentally efficient, reflecting [[consumer choice]]s and assigning to each agent his contribution to social welfare, is esteemed to be fundamentally correct.<ref>Kirzner (1981)</ref> Some non-neoclassical schools, like [[Post Keynesian economics|Post-Keynesians]], reject the neoclassical approach to [[value (economics)|value]] and distribution, but not because of their rejection of perfect competition as a reasonable approximation to the working of most product markets; the reasons for rejection of the neoclassical 'vision' are different views of the determinants of income distribution and of aggregated demand.<ref>Petri (2004)</ref> In particular, the rejection of perfect competition does not generally entail the rejection of free competition as characterizing most product markets; indeed it has been argued<ref>Clifton (1977)</ref> that competition is stronger nowadays than in 19th century capitalism, owing to the increasing capacity of big [[Conglomerate (company)|conglomerate]] firms to enter any industry: therefore the classical idea of a tendency toward a uniform rate of return on investment in all industries owing to free entry is even more valid today; and the reason why [[General Motors]], [[Exxon]] or [[NestlΓ©]] do not enter the computers or pharmaceutical industries is not insurmountable barriers to entry but rather that the rate of return in the latter industries is already sufficiently in line with the average rate of return elsewhere as not to justify entry. On this few economists, it would seem, would disagree, even among the neoclassical ones. Thus when the issue is normal, or long-period, product prices, differences on the validity of the perfect competition assumption do not appear to imply important differences on the existence or not of a tendency of rates of return toward uniformity as long as entry is possible, and what is found fundamentally lacking in the perfect competition model is the absence of marketing expenses and innovation as causes of costs that do enter normal average cost. The issue is different with respect to factor markets. Here the acceptance or denial of perfect competition in labour markets does make a big difference to the view of the working of market economies. One must distinguish neoclassical from non-neoclassical economists. For the former, absence of perfect competition in [[labour markets]], e.g. due to the existence of [[trade unions]], impedes the smooth working of competition, which if left free to operate would cause a decrease of wages as long as there were unemployment, and would finally ensure the full employment of labour: labour unemployment is due to absence of perfect competition in labour markets. Most non-neoclassical economists deny that a full flexibility of wages would ensure the full employment of labour and find a stickiness of wages an indispensable component of a market economy, without which the economy would lack the regularity and persistence indispensable to its smooth working. This was, for example, [[John Maynard Keynes]]'s opinion. Particularly radical is the view of the [[Piero Sraffa|Sraffian school]] on this issue: the labour demand curve cannot be determined hence a level of wages ensuring the equality between supply and demand for labour does not exist, and economics should resume the viewpoint of the classical economists, according to whom competition in labour markets does not and cannot mean indefinite price flexibility as long as supply and demand are unequal, it only means a tendency to equality of wages for similar work, but the level of wages is necessarily determined by complex sociopolitical elements; custom, feelings of justice, informal allegiances to classes, as well as overt coalitions such as trade unions, far from being impediments to a smooth working of labour markets that would be able to determine wages even without these elements, are on the contrary indispensable because without them there would be no way to determine wages.<ref>Garegnani (1990)</ref>
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Perfect competition
(section)
Add topic