Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main page
Recent changes
Random page
Help about MediaWiki
Special pages
Niidae Wiki
Search
Search
Appearance
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account
Log in
Pages for logged out editors
learn more
Contributions
Talk
Editing
Foundations of mathematics
(section)
Page
Discussion
English
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
Read
Edit
View history
General
What links here
Related changes
Page information
Appearance
move to sidebar
hide
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
== Ancient Greece == {{Further|Greek mathematics|Greek philosophy}} Most civilisations developed some mathematics, mainly for practical purposes, such as counting (merchants), [[surveying]] (delimitation of fields), [[Sanskrit prosody|prosody]], [[astronomy]], and [[astrology]]. It seems that [[ancient Greek philosophers]] were the first to study the nature of mathematics and its relation with the real world. [[Zeno of Elea]] ({{circa|490|430 BC}}) produced several paradoxes he used to support his thesis that movement does not exist. These paradoxes involve [[mathematical infinity]], a concept that was outside the mathematical foundations of that time and was not well understood before the end of the 19th century. The [[Pythagoreanism|Pythagorean school of mathematics]] originally insisted that the only numbers are natural numbers and ratios of natural numbers. The discovery ({{circa|5th century BC|lk=no}}) that the ratio of the diagonal of a square to its side is not the ratio of two natural numbers was a shock to them which they only reluctantly accepted. A testimony of this is the modern terminology of [[irrational number]] for referring to a number that is not the quotient of two integers, since "irrational" means originally "not reasonable" or "not accessible with reason".{{efn|See {{slink|Rational number#Etymology}} for this unusual terminology: "ratio" is derived from "rational", which is itself derived from "irrational".}} The fact that length ratios are not represented by rational numbers was resolved by [[Eudoxus of Cnidus]] (408β355 BC), a student of [[Plato]], who reduced the comparison of two irrational ratios to comparisons of integer multiples of the magnitudes involved. His method anticipated that of [[Dedekind cut]]s in the modern definition of real numbers by [[Richard Dedekind]] (1831–1916);<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://archive.org/details/thirteenbookseu00heibgoog/page/n136/mode/2up|title=The thirteen books of Euclid's Elements, edited by Sir Thomas Heath|publisher=[[Dover Publications]]|year=1956|isbn=0-486-60089-0|volume=2 (Book V)|location=New York|pages=124β126|translator-last=Heiberg}}</ref> see {{slink|Eudoxus of Cnidus#Eudoxus' proportions}}. In the ''[[Posterior Analytics]]'', [[Aristotle]] (384β322 BC) laid down the [[logic]] for organizing a field of knowledge by means of primitive concepts, axioms, postulates, definitions, and theorems. Aristotle took a majority of his examples for this from arithmetic and from geometry, and his logic served as the foundation of mathematics for centuries. This method resembles the modern [[axiomatic method]] but with a big philosophical difference: axioms and postulates were supposed to be true, being either self-evident or resulting from [[experiment]]s, while no other truth than the correctness of the proof is involved in the axiomatic method. So, for Aristotle, a proved theorem is true, while in the axiomatic methods, the proof says only that the axioms imply the statement of the theorem. Aristotle's logic reached its high point with [[Euclid]]'s [[Euclid's Elements|''Elements'']] (300 BC), a treatise on mathematics structured with very high standards of rigor: Euclid justifies each proposition by a demonstration in the form of chains of [[syllogisms]] (though they do not always conform strictly to Aristotelian templates). Aristotle's [[syllogistic logic]], together with its exemplification by Euclid's ''Elements'', are recognized as scientific achievements of ancient Greece, and remained as the foundations of mathematics for centuries.
Summary:
Please note that all contributions to Niidae Wiki may be edited, altered, or removed by other contributors. If you do not want your writing to be edited mercilessly, then do not submit it here.
You are also promising us that you wrote this yourself, or copied it from a public domain or similar free resource (see
Encyclopedia:Copyrights
for details).
Do not submit copyrighted work without permission!
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Search
Search
Editing
Foundations of mathematics
(section)
Add topic